English |ย ุงู„ุนุฑุจูŠุฉ | Tรผrkรงe | Urdu | Bahasa Indonesia

This article was originally published by the Yaqeen Institute. The original version can be found here.

Editor’s Note

This publication was scheduled for release before the news of the death of ISIS leader Abu Bakr Al-Baghdadi. In light of this news, we felt it even more important to release this paper to contrast the way the concept of the Caliphate lives in the Islamic tradition and many Muslim minds with the image in the Western imagination evoked by the brutality of ISIS.

Author Acknowledgments

I am indebted to a number of scholars and friends who painstakingly read earlier drafts of this essay and gave invaluable suggestions, even though I remain solely responsible for all the opinions and any lingering errors in it. These include Zara Khan, Jonathan Brown, Omar Anchassi, Mohammed El-Sayed Bushra, Carl Sharif El-Tobgui, and Mobeen Vaid, among others. Each of these went above and beyond to provide numerous line-by-line suggestions, corrections, and references. My heartfelt gratitude goes also to the leadership of Yaqeen who encouraged me to write on this challenging topic, and to the numerous students in various places from North America to nearly every Muslim country to whom I have taught this material in various formats, and whose questions, insights, and aspirations have been its real inspiration.

Who Wants the Caliphate?

A word loaded like no other, โ€œcaliphateโ€ summons deep memories and desires for some and ominous fears for others.ย For some fourteen centuries, notwithstanding some discontinuities, the Muslim world had been synonymous with the caliphate. Theย loss of the Ottoman Caliphate after the First World War sent convulsive waves of shock and lament throughout the lands of Islam,ย the idea of its return inspiring numerous movements and intellectual projects. Its lure, however, receded in the short-lived excitement of post-colonialย state-buildingย in the shadow of the Cold War. Today, as the failure of this state-buildingย becomes ever more spectacular, neoliberal economics and the global environmental collapse claim more victims, and the world system inches toward deglobalization and nativism, the idea of the caliphate as the only civilizational alternative that can safeguard the interests of the most vulnerable becomes stronger among Muslims globally. Although it is only beginning to attract scholarly attention, with every suppressed uprising in the Muslim world, every new cycle of terrorism and punitive war, every new Muslim population violated with impunity, and every new wall erected in Euro-America, the idea of a pan-Islamic union wins more converts.

A recent boost for the idea of a good caliphate was the rise of a bad one.ย The meteoric rise and ignominious fall of the so-called Islamic State in Iraq and Syria (ISIS; also known as ISIL: the Islamic State of Iraq and the Levant),ย with all its promiseย and horror, threw the potency of the idea into sharp relief. Even populist leaders in the region have gestured toward it, none more than Turkish President Recep Tayyip ErdoฤŸan who has capitalized on the growing global Muslim nostalgia for the Ottoman Caliphate. He recently declared that the Republic of Turkey is a continuation of the Ottoman Empire. โ€œSultan Erdogan,โ€ as he is affectionately called by his admirers, fills a void that many Muslims worldwide feel with increasing poignancy.1ย Although the Turkish presidentโ€™s power may be short-lived, the aspirations he has stirred up are not.

Not too long ago, the advocates of resurrecting the caliphate were cast, not always unfairly, as being fanatics, romanticists, or die-hard traditionalists, nostalgic for a golden age that critics claimed never was. Mainstream Islamists, increasingly inclined or compelled to embrace nation-state politics, had adopted positions ranging from a vision paralleling the secular Christian democratic politics of Europe to a sheepish acknowledgment that a union of Muslim, or at least Arab, countries, imagined as a confederation of Muslim democracies like the European Union, was indeed desirable, if virtually out of reach. Such pragmatists, for all their compromises, have largely failed in attaining their political goals or even avoiding massive persecution and, as the events after the Arab uprisings of 2011 show, seem to be losing the struggle for young Muslimsโ€™ imagination to newer, bolder visions. As the real and virtual images of the helplessness of Muslim masses and the betrayal of the Muslim elite circulate and grow, the idea of theย ummaโ€”the global community of Muslimsโ€”soars higher and sinks deeper, as does its natural complement, theย caliphate, a unified government to care for all Muslims, especially the forgotten ones on the margins. As these margins widen, far outweighing the fewer and fewer protected populations of the Muslim lands, the call grows shriller.

A recentย New York Timesย article sheds light on the continuing power of the idea of the caliphate among Muslims worldwide, including those who abhorred ISIS and categorically condemned its violence as well as its religious outlook. The caliphate, the author found during her investigation,ย โ€œwas an idea with more appeal than many in the West wanted to admit.โ€2ย The ensuing eventsโ€”the vile, self-serving politics of Middle Eastern despots and the deepening rifts of sectarian violenceโ€”seem to have led to โ€œa broad mainstream embrace of a collective Muslim identity that is global and overtly political and that has prompted young Muslims to view themselves as a collective community, for whom a homeland would provide solutions to trying circumstances.โ€3

The objections to the idea of resurrecting the caliphate, too, appear formidable. These are of three types: that it is undesirable, unfeasible, and/or religiously unnecessary. It isย undesirableย because it is a medieval, absolutist political system (if it can be called aย systemย at all); it beckons to a primitive age prior to human rights, progress, citizenship, democracy, and religious freedom. Moreover, it is associated with terrorist outfits like ISIS and draws the worst kind of attention from both its supporters and its adversaries. It isย unfeasibleย because the nation-state, whatever its flaws, is here to stay. Finally, it isย religiously unnecessaryย because the caliphate, it is claimed, is not an Islamic religious institution to begin with but only a historical institution and one that never even existed for long in its ideal form as a unified authority over all Muslims. In this essay, I evaluate these claims.

The controversy around the caliphate is animated in part by the ambiguity of its significance; it may invoke, especially to its detractors, an absolutist medieval theocracy of one-man-rule or, to its reformist supporters, a confederation of Muslim governments after the model of the European Union (one, presumably, with a happier ending!). To some, it is a premodern alternative to contemporary political systems; to others, a postmodern union of Muslim-majority democratic nation-states. Both of these types of views miss part of the complexity and richness of the Islamic discursive tradition around the caliphate and need to be engaged and deconstructed.

If understood as governance based on a just, accountable, human-rights-conscious, and decentralized union of the various Muslim regional governments with a unified economy and defense, it is my contention that the caliphateย may be the only way to avoid the further spiraling degradation of Muslim societies and states into terrorist fiefdoms and, God forbid, a third worldย war.ย 

ย The idea that the caliphateโ€”or the ideal caliphateโ€”is unfeasible simply because it no longer exists is based on little more than a failure of imagination and intellectual courage. Democracy, after all, began its life in a limited fashion in a small Greek city-state, flourished for a couple of hundred years, and then disappeared for the following two thousand years.4ย Even in its second incarnation, it emerged as a pejorative at first; the American Founding Fathers and the elite saw the idea of a โ€œrepublican democracyโ€ as an oxymoron but ultimately had to relent to popular pressures.5 There is no reason for an idea to be deemed unfeasible simply because it is not in vogue.

At a minimum,ย caliphateย means Muslim unity expressed in political terms, and as such, it is hardly an idea Muslims need to reinvent. ย It is present in every Qurโ€™anic lesson on social existence, every Prophetic teaching, and every Friday sermon to this day. Throughout history, Muslims have agreed on the need for a political actualization of this idea; it not only predated Islamic law but was a condition of its birth and coherence. In reality, the caliphate did not always include all Muslim regions, and the idea of a total pan-Islamic unity has been an aspiration only rarely attained. In this respect, the ideal caliphate is no different from the ideal of a perfect democracy or even a sovereign nation-state. Such collective aspirations are rarely realized in their ideal form, yet they inspire personal and collective moral action for the majority of humankind in any given era. I call such idealsย asymptotic ideals. An asymptote (fans of high-school Calculus will remember) is a line that approaches a curve but does not meet it at any finite distance.

An asymptotic ideal is not the same as a utopian ideal: it is real, rational, and even attainable at moments, but its perfection is always a work in progress. Political theorist Sheldon Wolin expresses the same idea when he uses adjectives such as โ€œepisodicโ€ and โ€œfugitiveโ€ to describe democracy.6ย All meaningful human ideals worth living for, including Islamโ€™s religious ideals, are asymptotic, like the Sunnah of the Beloved Prophet Muhammad, God grant him peace and blessings. Avoiding sin, always preferring God over all else, and being truthful, just, and courageous are all part of the same asymptotic ideal. Oneโ€™s asymptotic ideals, I contend, are the truest indication of oneโ€™s faith. True believers in democracy, liberalism, capitalism, or socialism are those who hold on to them even when they seem to be failing. The political unity of Muslims and the continuity of Prophetic governance is one such ideal that has been a part of Muslim identity throughout history and is based, I will show below, in the imperatives of Islam.

The caliphate was not a utopia even in its best days; we must, therefore, reject the romanticization of the caliphate as an institution that can magically, merely by dint of a declaration, guarantee Muslimsโ€™ independence and well-being. Nor did it last continuously and unproblematically throughout its thirteen centuries of existence. Some critics, however, hold the historical caliphate grounded in fourteen centuries of consensus to such exacting ideals that would not leave any political or religious institution or ideal standing.ย Clearly, the consensus in Islam on the prohibition of perjury, usury, the killing of the innocent, etc. has not meant that these norms have always been upheld in practice.ย This selective skepticism reminds one of the Kharijite ferocity toward other Muslims. They, too, had first created a false ideal arbitrarilyโ€”the Qurโ€™an alone, as they understood it, without the aid of the living authorities who had seen it revealedโ€”and then condemned all whom they judged to have fallen short. Specifically, the Kharijites abhorred the imperfect governance by the caliphs and even leaders of their own sects. If the fact that past caliphates were not fully unified and not always just is taken to mean that no caliphate existed, we could argue by analogy that there have been no Muslims in history because they have all been imperfect, just as there exists no democracy because all democracies are imperfect. All such arguments are equally absurd.

There are, of course, modern secularists who have argued that the political autonomy and unity of Muslims, as implied in the idea of the caliphate, are not desirable goals or religious ideals to begin with. To such arguments we turn presently. The point made so far is that merely pointing to historical imperfections is hardly an argument against the feasibility of the caliphate.ย The question of feasibility, admittedly, is an important element in evaluating and prioritizing obligations in Islamic jurisprudence and, rather than dismissing it out of hand, we must argue for it, as we begin to do in this essay.

Next, there is the question of desirability. For the believers, the question of desirability is always subordinated to the question of the divine command. After all, Godโ€™s commands are for our ultimate well-being even when we cannot see it: โ€œGod knows and you know not.โ€7ย Any particular command of God, however, is to be understood within an edifice of Islamic jurisprudence that consists of commands, prohibitions, and recommendations arranged (differently by different scholars) in terms of pragmatic priorities, individual and collective capacities, and epistemological certitude about its status. In the following, we briefly address the status of establishing the caliphate as a command, an exhaustive treatment being beyond our scope.

Some leading scholars of Islam, like Hujjat al-Islam al-Ghazali, have considered the caliphate an obligation regardless of its efficacy, like a religious ritual, thus separating it from its political functionality or utility. Others, like Shaykh al-Islam Ibn Taymiyya and Imam al-Haramayn al-Juwayni, have emphasized its rational nature. This latter view, I believe, is more compelling. Any movement toward reenacting such a global institution must make a compelling case for its ability to address pressing political, social, economic, and ecological challenges confronting Muslims. Any attempt to transcend the existing state of affairsโ€”which we shall identify as the nation-state systemโ€”in favor of pan-Islamic unification in the Muslim world would have to engage in a long and hard dialogue about these problems. Such an endeavor, moreover, would have to involve in this dialogue and rebuilding not only all Muslims, especially the disadvantaged and disenfranchised, but also non-Muslim citizens of Muslim lands, regional neighbors, and the global scholarly and scientific community.

In summary, to argue for its religious obligation, we must invoke scripture and Islamic jurisprudential tradition, but to make a case for its feasibility and desirability, one must also turn to history and politics (the so-calledย fiqh al-wฤqiสฟ). In reality, on this as on any given issue, these two types of discourse must proceed dialectically between jurisprudence and reality. If the case is properly made with these considerations in mind, I submit, the outcome will be preferable to most well-meaning people worldwide, not just Muslims.

There are more and more compelling grounds to make such a case today. Over the past few decades, globalization has enormously increased Muslimsโ€™ awareness of other Muslims and of their unity of circumstance and vision across the globe. At the same time, the gap between the haves and the have-nots has increased tremendously in every society. The Arab uprisings of 2011 threw into sharp relief the commonality of the public sphere of nearly two dozen Arabic-speaking countries. The convulsions of these uprisings are far from over. At the same time, the ensuing tragedies in nearly every country have demonstrated the vacuity of national sovereignty, as oil-based monarchies and military autocrats across national boundaries closed ranks against the popular protest movements. Too came tumbling down the facade of the clerical establishments that happily cheered on the massacres and imprisonments. Under the crushing weight of utter political illegitimacy and the bankruptcy of the clerical establishment, Muslim societies are becoming increasingly incapable of providing for decent human life, and reactions to such unbearable conditions include endemic violence (this includes terrorism, but more importantly, broken individuals and communities that are also more vulnerable to microaggressions and domestic violence), religious disillusionment or fanaticism, and general ethical cynicism.8

Globally, the nation-state model has been unraveling since the promulgation of the neoliberal policies of the 1980s by global powers. This anxiety has been evident in influential titles that have appeared since the 1990s, such as โ€œThe End of the Nation-Stateโ€ (several monographs carry this telling title, discussed below), โ€œThe Clash of Civilizations,โ€9ย Jihad vs. McWorld: How Globalism and Tribalism are Reshaping the World,10ย andย Endgames: Questions in Late Modern Political Thought.11ย This literature speaks of the dissolution of the traditional nation-state and the rise instead of global capitalists in cahoots with regional strongmen bent on amassing wealth and securing their power at the expense of increasing numbers and classes of people. These forces have together repurposed the apparatus of the nation-state. Even in its best days (from the nineteenth century until the Second World War), the nation-state consisted of an alignment of particular interests behind the faรงade of an abstracted international system. A leading American scholar of international relations at Stanford University aptly captured this idea in his bookย Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisy.12ย The supposed sovereignty of weaker states, his work shows, has been routinely violated by global powers, but the fiction has been useful in maintaining just the right kinds of puppets in power. Much of the literature concerning the end of the nation-state points out the inability of this system to deal with the greatestย crisesย of our times, from man-made climate change and income inequality to the growing refugee crisis (the rise of non-citizens), and recommends regional or global economic cooperation as the way out.13ย The irony of it all is that Muslims have historically benefited the least from the Industrial Revolution but are going to be the first targets of its inevitable consequence, environmental catastrophe. โ€œWe’re headed for โ€˜climate apartheid,โ€™ in which the poor will suffer while the rich save themselves, warns a chilling UN report.โ€14ย Muslims can be sure that this scenario is going to play out in its most infernal form in the petty kingdoms and military states that they inhabit.ย In short, for Muslims, the nation-state system has been, and will continue to be, particularly brutal, divisive, and infernal. This is so not only because it was calculated by the outgoing colonizers from the outset to divide them and control their resources, but also, as we show below, because it is structurally incompatible withย Islam.15

Dreams, pasts, and futures

Humans are creatures of memories and desires. Life without hope that transcends the present, without dreams of improving oneโ€™s condition and equally of saving others that we love, is a dreadful nightmare. Such dystopian hopelessness has often birthed great evil. Even great imperialists have recognized the need for dreams; Churchill once said that if one was not a Marxist by the age of twenty-five, one had no heart, but if one was still a Marxist by thirty-five, one had no brain. Marxism has been the ultimate secular religion of the modern age, complete with an eschatology and creed. ย To the secular youth of the Global North, Marxism or some other form of progressive vision fills the vacuum left by religious eschatology and world-saving compassion that capitalism lacks. Inasmuch as Muslims are a global community, they must possess worthy shared dreams and hopes. The Orwellian control of official religion and extermination of any expression of alternative visions of Islam by the reigning despots in the Muslim world is directly responsible for the apocalypticism and nihilistic destructiveness evident in the likes of ISIS. The despots at home are aided and complemented by the global War on Terror and demonization by world powers of anything but the most emasculated Islam. This state of affairs has devastated the psyche of an entire generation of millennial Muslims by polarizing them between those who feel sorry for being Muslim and others who feel angry for the same reason.

The kind of Islam that is sustainable in the future must be one that is at home with itself while being able to save the world not from itself, but by being itself. This vision is powerfully articulated by Professor Salman Sayyid in his bold, imaginative workย Recalling the Caliphate:

“Recalling the caliphate means understanding that the challenges that confront Muslims collectively are neither religious nor cultural but political, and their resolution can only be found in a politics in the name of Islam. This politics has no necessary content other than that struggled over in the historical sequence inaugurated by the return of the Prophet Muhammad (pbuh) [from his ascension to the heaven] โ€ฆ Recalling the caliphate, then, is a decolonial declaration, it is a reminder that Islam is Islam, and for Muslims that is all it needs to be.”16

The call is long overdue. For nearly a century now, Islam has not been allowed to be Islam.

After the Cold War, the western order triumphed. Its prophets, from conservatives like Huntington (โ€œOthers are different, we must fight allโ€) to liberals like Fukuyama (โ€œWe are the end of history, we must assimilate allโ€), recognized the need for new frontiers and new enemies. Liberalism (like its economic twin, capitalism) constantly needs empire and conquest, and its triumph has nearly flattened the world, leaving liberals themselves sometimes wondering whether another kind of life is possible. Anthropologist Clifford Geertz agonized over this dilemma: his belief in the superiority of liberalism and his awareness, as an anthropologist, of genuine and irreducible diversity of human beliefs and cultures. His colleague, Richard Shweder, builds on this tension and poses a compelling question: given the current flattening of all civilizations by liberal capitalism, is our Brave-New-World-like monoculture the only possible human future? He boldly speculates three possible futures, inviting us to note that:

“it remains to be seen whether history will come to an end with the apotheosis of a universal civilization (prophecy #1), the universal triumph of ethnonationalism with its many separated and autonomous nation (based)-states (prophecy #2), or whether human beings, having lived in multinational empires many times before the modern era, are ready to do so again, even on politically liberal terms (prophecy #3).”17

It is the third possible future, he suggests, that alone ensures real human prosperity and liberty. And this is the only one, I contend, that Muslims can reasonably embrace: a world of genuinely different civilizations, but ones that see collaboration and coexistence, not clash, as their constant, renewing aim.

Its false universalism is liberalismโ€™s greatest aporia and its greatest hypocrisy. As Wael Hallaq has perceptively argued in his recent monographย Restating Orientalism: A Critique of Modern Knowledge,18ย those like Edward Said who opposed this belligerence of the โ€œclashโ€ did so by eliminating Islam as a civilizational reality. A rather more fruitful approach is to embrace Islam as a civilizational entity and question, rather, the seeming inevitability of โ€œclash.โ€

The flowing blood

โ€œAcross the world, genocidal states are attacking Muslims,โ€ reads the title of an opinion piece by sociologist Arjun Appadurai, โ€œIs Islam really their target?โ€ And the by-line reads: โ€œAs Israel incarcerates Palestinians and Myanmar drives out its Rohingyas, a reflection on the predicament of ethnic and racial biominorities.โ€19ย Welcome to the club, I thought. For decades, this has been the question Muslims have asked themselves; most have no doubt about the answer. The piece ends with no great insight, but it is the banality of the observationโ€”one made by an Indian-American sociologist, not an al-Qaeda operative ready to blow things up in revengeโ€”that caught my attention.ย The banality of Muslim blood, that is.

As Muslim-majority nation-states, along with others in the developing world, fail or become otherwise uninhabitable, the Global North erectsย walls.ย Faced with war, colonialism, genocide, corruption, pollution, and/or starvation, Muslims worldwideโ€”even those only nominally religious in their personal livesโ€”readily sign up for a modern pan-Islamism that would protect them from these shared indignities. In a globalized world where the Westโ€™s War on Terror20ย has, paradoxically, accentuated the Muslimness of Muslims everywhere, Israel, China, Myanmar, India, and countless other states feel free to deal with their โ€œMuslim problemโ€ with total impunity. โ€œOur conflict is with the entire Muslim world, with the entire Arab world,โ€ declared an Israeli politician, echoing the anti-Islam sentiment in Euro-America and elsewhere.21ย Muslims are inevitably reminded of the warning of the Prophet, Allahโ€™s peace and blessings be upon him, that nations will feast on them one day, and not because they will be few but because their great numbers will be worthless like the straw carried by a torrent.22

The problem is not new, and it is not about to go away. Already at the end of the Cold War, pundits had declared Islam to be a problem for the Westโ€™s total cultural hegemony. โ€œIslam has bloody borders,โ€ declared Samuel Huntington in his epoch-making 1993 article โ€œThe Clash of Civilizations.โ€23ย Huntington credited his inspiration for the idea to writers on both sides of the Islamโ€“west divide. He quotes a secular Indian Muslim who wrote, โ€œIt is in the sweep of the Islamic nations from the Maghreb to Pakistan that the struggle for a new world order will begin,โ€ and Bernard Lewis, who wrote, โ€œThis is no less than a clash of civilizationsโ€”the perhaps irrational but surely historic reaction of an ancient rival against our Judeo-Christian heritage, our secular present, and the worldwide expansion of both.โ€ Lewisโ€™s and Huntingtonโ€™s vision was belligerent, inaccurate, and uncharitable, but it had an element of realism that has triumphed over the thousands of academic protests contending that there was no such clash because, they contended, there were no distinct civilizations. There are.

Since Huntington wrote, the borders have only gotten bloodier, but not just the borders. Beyond the borders, the inner organs of the body of which the Prophet Muhammad ๏ทบ spoke are failing and bleeding as the body attacks itself.ย Palestine is being shot and bled to death by an ethnoreligious, colonizing apartheid state. The Rohingya are being burned, raped, and annihilated by another ethnoreligious, nationalist state as Rohingyan mothers are birthing en masse the children of their Myanmar rapists. The Kashmiris and millions of Indian Muslims are being deprived daily of their dignity, humanity, and life by yet another religiously-inspired ethnic nationalism. In China, the Uyghur Muslims are being exterminated in torture and brainwashing camps, where their men are killed while their women are forced to cohabit with Han Chinese men.ย To date, not a single Muslim-majority state in the region has strongly protestedโ€”even the Muslim street has been silentโ€”and the only significant outcry comes from secular human rights groups and, increasingly, from states that are strategically hostile to the rise of China. Muslims in the Central African Republic are being ethnically cleansed.24ย Yemen, Syria, Libya, Iraq, Somalia, Sudan, and Afghanistan are embroiled in civil wars or deep unrest with no end in sight.

The regional struggle between paper-tigers made of fossil fuels, Saudi Arabia and Iranโ€”portrayed as a sectarian Shiสฟaโ€“Sunni conflict by embattled elites on both sides looking for distractions from their inadequaciesโ€”could catapult the entire region into an atrocious regional war that could easily pull in the rest of the world. The biggest hurdles on the way to unification and collaboration are also the precise reasons that they must be brought about.

An absolutist theocracy or a tolerant Islamic union?

For any defense of the caliphate to be meaningful, the frequent failures of Muslim political thought and practice in the past would have to be candidly acknowledged and systematically distinguished from an authentic and feasible vision of a Muslim political union in the modern world. Such a vision cannot afford to be ahistorical, nor utopian, nor a mere recapitulation of one medieval treatise or institution or another. Furthermore, such a union must guarantee meaningful and robust accommodation of local variations of political arrangements, cultures, and religious denominations among Muslims and the rights of non-Muslim minorities. The task of delineating and imagining such a vision requires not an essay but a generation of Muslim jurists, theologians, political theorists entrepreneurs, and visionary leaders. What I offer here is a modest justification and some imaginative delineation of this vision in broad strokes, starting with a little history.

Professor David Wasserstein, a scholar of Judaism and Islam of Jewish heritage at Vanderbilt University, recently published a study on the ideological and religious roots of ISIS and its caliphate,ย Black Banners of ISIS: The Roots of the New Caliphate.25ย A few years earlier, he also delivered an enlightening address in which he argued that it was medieval Islamโ€”the Islam of the Old Caliphate, that isโ€”that saved Judaism from extinction.

“Islam saved Jewry. This is an unpopular, discomforting claim in the modern world. But it is a historical truth. The argument for it is double. First, in 570 CE, when the Prophet Mohammad was born, the Jews and Judaism were on the way to oblivion. And second, the coming of Islam saved them, providing a new context in which they not only survived, but flourished, laying foundations for subsequent Jewish cultural prosperity โ€“ also in Christendom โ€“ through the medieval period into the modern world. . . .ย Had Islam not come along, Jewry in the west would have declined to disappearance and Jewry in the east would have become just another oriental cult.”26

It is not clear if the irony is obvious to the professor. The historical caliphate was a precondition for the existence of Islamic civilization, one that produced the law, theology, and religious vision that, despite is imperfections (remember the asymptote!), protected intellectually vibrant communities of Christianity and Judaism and hosted the renaissance of Hellenistic science and philosophy. Before we dismiss this fact with a hasty โ€œEnough with that nostalgia!โ€ and โ€œYou cannot turn back the wheels of time,โ€ it behooves us to stay with the contrast between Wassersteinโ€™s two examples a bit longer. Had the caliphate not existed and presided over the centuries-long unified reign over far-flung lands characterized by relative peace, stability, and cultural and commercial exchange, and had the unity of the lands it conquered ended as quickly after the Prophet ๏ทบ as it was gained, the alternative would have been a dark age of little kingdoms or, worse, tribal vendettas presided over by the likes of the Kharijites (a fitting analog of todayโ€™s ISIS). Neither the Umayyads, nor the Abbasids, nor the Ottomans were perfect caliphsโ€”some were downright tyrantsโ€”but on the whole, they and the Muslim religious and political elite all recognized the paramount value of the unity of the community and the primacy of law and order. It is this consensual ideal cherished by the learned Muslim to which we now turn.

The past: History and normative tradition

The word โ€œcaliphateโ€ is the anglicized version of the Arabicย khilฤfa. Its triliteral root (khaสพ-lฤm-fฤสพ) connotes the idea of โ€œbeing or coming after or behind someone in terms of order, time, or space.โ€ Aย khalฤซfaย (caliph), then, is a successor, someone literally left behind by a predecessor to fulfill a certain responsibility. The Qurโ€™an speaks of Adam and by implication his progeny as โ€œkhalฤซfaโ€ (2:30)โ€”which the earliest exegetes naturally took to mean โ€œsuccessor of an earlier creation that once dominated the earth.โ€ But God is also, according to a famous supplication of the Prophet Muhammad ๏ทบ inย Sahih Muslim, theย khalฤซfaย of a traveler who leaves his home and family in Godโ€™s care.27 This usage suggests that the modern translation of the โ€œcaliphโ€ as โ€œdeputyโ€ or โ€œvicegerentโ€ is imprecise, as is the idea popularized in the twentieth century that the humans are metaphysical โ€œvicegerents of God.โ€ Another reference in the Qurโ€™an to the Prophet David, upon him be peace, as โ€œkhalฤซfaย in the land,โ€ simply meant โ€œinheritor of the land,โ€ but has been similarly used to impute to the word a sense of political authority and metaphysical stewardship of the earth. The metaphysical meaning is conceptually justifiable through the Qurโ€™anic notions ofย taskhฤซrย andย takrฤซmย (that God has honored humans and subdued all other creation for them, 17:70, 14:32-3, etc.), but linguistically, it has no necessary relation to the term at hand,ย khalฤซfa.ย This is not merely a linguistic quibble; entire genres of literature both by Muslim authors and Orientalists have emerged based on this misunderstanding.28ย In certain cases, this misunderstanding has been used to impute to the Qurโ€™an the modern idea of popular sovereignty in the nation-state.29

What we are interested in, however, is the historical use of the term to signify the supreme political ruler of the Muslims. In this sense,ย khalฤซfaย (caliphate) came to mean the deputyship (niyฤba) of the Prophet Muhammad ๏ทบ in the leadership and stewardship of his community after his death. This supreme political leader of Muslims was also calledย imamย (leader) by theologians both Sunni and Shiสฟaโ€”although the Shiสฟa reserved the termย imam for their theologically rightful, and not necessarily political, leader. Earlier on, precisely because the termย khalฤซfaย did not have a clear political meaning and was only a description of Abu Bakrโ€™s role as the successor to the Prophet ๏ทบ, the more explicit label ofย amฤซr al-muสพminฤซnย (the commander of the believers) became the common way to address the ruler since the reign of the Second Caliph, สฟUmar. Over time, when the political field became crowded with different kinds of leaders such asย amฤซrย (military commander),ย sulแนญฤnย (authority, king) andย malikย (king), historical and political usage settled on the termย khalฤซfaย to refer to the single, supreme leader of all Muslims.

The five historical models of the caliphate

The first and only normative model of the caliphate for the Sunni majority comprises the first four successors of the Prophet ๏ทบ, who later came to be called theย Rashidunย (Rightly Guided). At first, religious and political authorities were not systematically distinguished and the caliph or successor of the Prophet embodied both. Less than a century later, another model emerged in which the caliphate became a primarily political office, and religious authority gradually came to be shared between the caliph and the scholars (สฟulamฤสพ). Theย สฟulamฤสพ, the emerging class of dedicated scholars, now increasingly served as the real socio-religious leaders of urban Muslim communities and intellectual schools. The caliphโ€™s powers had never been absolute in practice, but theย สฟulamฤสพย began to theorize such limits and functions starting in the fourth/tenth century.

The early caliphs ruled the worldโ€™s largest empire from the small town of Medina as first among equals (primus inter pares). This egalitarian, direct-access, and piety-based model proved unscalable to the needs of administering a vast, far-flung empire. It thus gave way to theย imperial caliphateย of the late Umayyad and High Abbasid eras. At its height, during the second/eighth and third/ninth centuries, the Baghdad-based Abbasid caliphate was the richest and largest empire the world had ever seen in terms of per capita wealth.30ย It also adopted the symbolism of the pre-Islamic Sassanid empire in which a worthy emperor, in order to dispense total justice, had to project an absolutist, god-like aura. The actual powers of the caliph, both in reality and in the Law of Islam, were rather limited, and in some cases drastically so. This was the second model of the caliphate.

As the actual power of the Baghdadi caliphs waned, aย thirdย model arose in which the caliph was primarily a symbolic and spiritual authority; the actual rulers of various provinces were often local governors or invading military commanders who, lacking inherent legitimacy, paid homage to the caliph. This age lasted for some five centuries. It is in thisย classicalย era that Islamic law, theology, and political thought crystallized. The caliphโ€™s symbolic power was indispensable, and the possibility of its recovery of actual power was not far-fetched. The famous twelfth-century Islamic hero, แนขalฤแธฅ al-Dฤซn (Saladin), who took Jerusalem back from the Crusaders and won hearts by showing great magnanimity, died seeking but not attaining the approval of the caliph in Baghdad; the caliphโ€™s approval mattered for a rulerโ€™s authority to be legitimate, no matter his accomplishments.

The caliph, it became increasingly clear to Muslims, represented two crucial continuities for the Muslim umma: (1) the symbolic connection back to the Prophet ๏ทบ and the Rightly Guided caliphs, whose conduct remained the gold standard, and (2) the spatial continuity (or unity) of all Muslims, who now lived in networked societies stretching over parts of Africa, Asia, and Europe and ruled by various local kings and governors. These two continuities made political fragmentation, religious sectarianism, and cultural rivalries manageable, averting the worst centrifugal tendencies and preventing a collapse of the region into constant warfare and savagery. These societies were largely self-governed by the Law of Islam as administered by local rulers and scholars. The kings or sultans served as โ€˜butlersโ€™ or, moreย grandiosely, as the executive branch, who were important for defense and upkeep of the Law but nevertheless disposable. They came and went without changing the norms, laws, or institutions of this mega-society. This third model has been called โ€œclassical Islamic constitutionalism.โ€31ย It is important because, with the exception of the first couple of centuries, it is what the caliphate has actually looked like throughout most of Islamic history.

Things were far from perfect, and the most influentialย สฟulamฤสพย who deliberated on political matters, from al-Mawardiย (d. 450/1058), al-Juwayni (d. 478/1085), al-Ghazali (d. 505/1111), to Ibn Taymiyya (d. 728/1328), considered the actual loss of the caliphโ€™s power to military usurpers unacceptable, though they deemed it tolerable as an exceptional situation. Al-Ghazali likened accepting the Saljuq sultans of his time, who only nominally accepted the supreme authority of the Abbasid caliph but in fact flouted his authority, to the eating of carrion: it was permitted only to save life in the absence of wholesome food. Others, in particular Ibnย Taymiyya, agreed, as we shall see below. During the first half of this model before the Mongol attack in 656/1258, the Baghdad-based caliphโ€™s symbolic power was significant, but even afterward in the Mamluk period, when the Abbasid caliph, now in Cairo, lost all power, in distant Muslim lands such as Delhi and Timbuktu, his letter of investiture was crucial to marking the difference between mere usurpation of power and legitimacy and belonging to the Muslim body politic.

A fourth model of the caliphate, which was an amalgam of the second and third ones, came to the fore when the Ottomans politically united Eastern Europe, Western Asia, and North Africa under one empire that lasted for about four hundred years as one of the most successful, stable, and powerful empires of the time. The Ottoman sultans (who took on the title โ€œcaliphโ€ after defeating the Mamluks in Cairo), upheld the Shariสฟa Law that was expounded and administered by the scholars as muftis and judges. The caliph-sultanโ€™s powers, therefore, were limited. We have cases of sultans who were deposed because of the verdict of the chiefย qadiย (judge). Yet the sultans could gain power and act despotically as well, flouting Islamic norms on matters that touched on their crucial interests. In contrast to the Ottomans in the Middle East and North Africa and to the Mughals in India, who ruled over a Hindu majority, theirย Shiสฟa rivals, the Safavids, based their legitimacy on strong theocratic claims. The Ottoman claim to the caliphate was at times imagined in mystical ways. Anatolian Sufism helped imagine the Ottoman caliph as a ruler, spiritual guide, and lawmaker for all Muslims, even though no political effort was madeโ€”and was perhaps unthinkableโ€”to join the three vast Muslim empires into one political order.32

The crucial common factor in the last three models of the caliphate is that the caliph did not wield religious authority except in limited public matters. For the Ottomans, the mystics could imagine the caliph to be Godโ€™s shadow on earth, and even the occult could be used to make prophecies and justify policies, but the Hanafi legal establishment, the backbone of the empire, ensured that such claims remained within the Sufi lodges. Bernard Lewis, the famous hawkish neo-conservative doyen of Orientalist studies, acknowledged this much: there has been and can be no theocracy in (Sunni) Islam. This is thanks to the inherent epistemological pluralism of Sunni jurisprudence and the lack of any institution like the medieval Church to speak for God. The multiplicity of voices interpreting scripture and tradition meant two things: that religious authority was divided and polyphonic and that the ruling elite could never control the religious authority, and as a result, an organic system of socio-religious checks and balances emerged.

The third and fourth models of the caliphate, which lasted a combined total of a thousand years, were, in short, neither theocratic nor absolutist. They guaranteed a large measure of freedom to communities under their rule: Muslims of different rites, Jews, Christians, and others could live as relatively free communities. Although far from perfect, this system worked more effectively in facilitating a fair and God-centered life than modern Muslim states and even many democracies. Unlike the modern liberal model, communities and hence communal norms were deemed necessary for any decent human existence, which is why even non-Muslims were free to live by the religious norms in which they believed. The needle of the balance between individual and communal rights tilted often in the latter direction. The Ottomans, like the Romans had been vis-ร -vis the Greeks, were administrators and institution builders, and turned the Qurโ€™anic model of protected communities,ย dhimmis, into an institution of multiple religious communities represented by their leaders in the capital. This became known as theย milletย system.33

When the modern nation-states of the nineteenth century confronted the Ottomans, for the first time becoming their equals and quickly surpassing Ottoman economic and military might, the Ottomans adjusted and ultimately made great strides in modernizing their army, economy, and societyโ€”in that orderโ€”in a relatively short time. The old organic, socially, and communally grounded limits on the sultanโ€™s power were replaced with a constitution, but the Ottomans did not survive the First World War. Modern historians have suggested that the old idea of an unsustainably decrepit regimeโ€”the idea of the Ottoman Empire as the โ€œsick man of Europeโ€โ€”was incorrect; in fact, the Ottomans could have survived had they bet on a different side in the war or somehow survived it. We might call this short-lived constitutional caliphateย a fifth potential model of the caliphate.

The theory of the caliphate

Trying to separate the essence of the caliphate from its various manifestations, the Sunni tradition theorized the caliphate meticulously, establishing the foundation of its obligation, its functions, nature, and limits, and responding to its transformations while also trying to stay true to theย Rashidunย model. This was a complex exercise; every disagreement that could be conceived was had, and the leading jurist-theologians built and continually rethought a careful edifice of proofs and justifications. Unsurprisingly, careful theorization of the institution took place first at the hands of the Sunniย ulamaย in the fifth/eleventh century precisely when the institutionโ€™s existence was threatened. The sheer necessity of the caliphate for the continued unity and existence of the religious community during the first two centuries made extensive theoretical defense superfluous, even though we find one of the earliest preserved epistles in Islam, that of the Umayyad secretary สฟAbd al-แธคamฤซd al-Kฤtib (d. 132/750), concerned with theorizing and defending the caliphate as a divinely mandated institution that continued the Prophetโ€™s mission.34

All surviving Muslim schools and sects agreed on the obligation of appointing one leader for the Muslim community. The Sunnis and the Shiสฟa agreed on this point but their conceptions of the office differed. The Imami Shiสฟa included belief in an imamโ€”a chosen scion of theย Alidย familyโ€”in the very definition of faith, and an obligation upon God (as a matter ofย luแนญf, or divine grace), which meant that knowing and believing in one true imam (even if he was not in power or physically existent) to be an obligation upon all humans.35ย The Zaydi Shiสฟa believed in the right to rule of a scion of the Alid family, but one who showed his fitness for the office by successfully rebelling against unjust rule and claiming leadership. The Sunnis, in contrast, considered establishing the caliphate to be a collective obligation. The difference is subtle: for the Shiสฟa, not believing in the right imam is heretical and may evenย invalidateย oneโ€™s faith; for the Sunnis, failing to install a rightful imam or failing to strive to do so is sinful. The Ibฤแธฤซsโ€”the moderate and the only Kharijite sect to survive past the formative periodโ€”believe in the obligation of a just imam/caliph, but, unlike the Shiสฟa and most Sunnis, and like most post-Ottoman Sunnis, they do not require that the candidate be from Quraysh or any particular lineage.36

Opinions varied as to the possibility of Islamic life without a caliph. Some, like al-Ghazali, went so far as to deny the legitimacy of Islamic life under such conditions. Others, like his teacher and the chief Ashสฟari theologian and Shฤfiสฟฤซ jurist of his time Abลซ al-Maสฟฤlฤซ al-Juwayni, considered such a scenario in his brilliant, imaginative treatiseย Ghiyฤth al-umam fฤซ-l-tiyฤth al-แบ“ulam.37ย There he imagines dystopian futures in which Muslims may not have a caliph with proper qualifications, or no caliph at all, leaving the scholars to lead the community, and finally, the absence even of qualified scholars and instructions about what Muslims might do in such cases. Not satisfied with citing a few indirect verses and solitary (ฤแธฅฤd) แธฅadiths, he insists that since the definitive obligation of the caliphate requires absolute proof, it must be established on the basis of the consensus of the Companions, the highest imaginable authority for a religious obligation.38ย He argues that numerous rational people cannot agree on an answer to a question that accepts multiple rational answers unless there is a reason, and that reason in the case of the Companions must have been their shared understanding of the teachings of the Qurโ€™an and the Prophetย ๏ทบ. The consensus, therefore, was neither accidental nor one born out of mere necessity. As the initial disagreement of the Medinan Helpers (Anแนฃฤr) in their meeting at the Portico of Banลซ Sฤสฟida shows, it was arrived at after deliberation as Abลซ Bakr and สฟUmar saw clearly, and everyone subsequently agreed, that its need was created by the indubitable obligations of Islam.

In the post-Mongol period (seventh/thirteenth-century onward), the earlier tendency to pragmatically justify usurping strongmen in conditions of dire urgency and insecurity led to the justification of any usurper who could defend the community or some part of it. The most original writers of this period, including both Ibn Khaldun and Ibn Taymiyya, asserted the obligation of the caliphate but also broke new ground in political thinking. Ibn Khaldun theorized the social, material, and psychological bases of political power, thus giving birth to a theory of history and politics several centuries before such thinking became common in the modern period. Ibn Taymiyya, without questioning the obligation of the caliphate, recognized the utter inefficacy of the post-Mongol caliphate and sought to recover communal vibrancy and an ascending political model in which upholding the Shariสฟa became the central dimension of the rulerโ€™s legitimacy. Before the Mongol destruction of Baghdad, the caliphate was seen as having created the world in which the Shariสฟa could be articulated and developed. This fact, coupled with the caliphateโ€™s claim of continuity to the Prophetย ๏ทบ,ย was stronger than any particular scriptural justification: the caliphate had been bigger than the Shariสฟa. Theย สฟulamฤสพ, like al-Mawardi and al-Ghazali, provided proof for the caliphate only when they felt it was threatened. Now, in the post-Mongol world, it was the Shariสฟa that provided the impetus to create Islamic governments everywhere until the proper caliphate could be restored. Ibn Taymiyya provided only the first arguments for such Islamic politics; scholars from all schools subsequentlyโ€”and especially in Ottoman political thoughtโ€”recognized this natural development of โ€œShariสฟa politics.โ€39

To give substance and texture to the claims just put forth, let us consider a sampling of the types of claims and justifications for the caliphate provided by scholars from a broad range of schools.ย The encyclopedic แบ’ฤhirฤซ scholar Ibn แธคazm (d. 456/1064), writing in Spain and hence outside of the traditional lands of the Abbasid caliphate, noted:

“Allย Ahl al-Sunnah, all Murjiสพa, all Shiสฟa, and all Kharijites have agreed unanimously on the obligation of the Imamate and that the Ummah has an obligation to obey a just Imam who establishes the rulings ofย God overย them, managing their affairs with the Law brought by the Messenger of God. The only exception are the Najadฤt of the Kharijites, who said that people have no obligation to have an imam; it is upon them, rather, to fulfill each otherโ€™s rights.”40

Ibn แธคazmโ€™s reference is to a handful of radicals during the Second Civil War (AH 60โ€“70s), when the Kharijites and a few Muสฟtazila could even question the obligation of the caliphate in the heady days of early schisms. But then, even basic doctrines such as the authority of the hadith, the validity of rational analogy, the righteousness of the last two Rashidun caliphs, and even the sanctity of Muslim life were fair game for these groups. One such free-thinker argued almost counter-factually: if all believers volunteered to live by the divine law, no government would be necessary. Note that he did not suggest a secular government as an alternative, but denied the need for a political order altogether. Another argued, almost hyper-factually, that this no-imam situation applied only in times of civil war, and allegiance to no imam was necessary during one.41ย On the whole, however, the necessity of a caliph was far more unproblematically and unanimously agreed upon than many other doctrines now taken to be fundamental.

The Creed (al-สฟAqฤสพidย al-Nasafiyya) of the leading Hanafi-Maturidi authority Abลซ แธคafแนฃ al-Nasafฤซ (d. 537/1142) reads: โ€œMuslims must have an imam to enforce their rulings, establishย แธฅudลซd, and defend borders โ€ฆ .โ€ Commenting on this, the Persian polymath and Ashสฟari theologian al-Taftฤzฤnฤซ (d. 792/1390) wrote:

“There is consensus that installing an imam is an obligation. The disagreement is on whether the obligation is upon God or upon creation, by revelational evidence or rational. And [our] school holds that it is an obligation upon the creation through revelation, as the Prophet ๏ทบ said, โ€œWhoever dies without knowing the imam of his time dies in pre-Islamic ignorance,โ€42ย which is why the Ummah made the installing of an imam their utmost concern, even before his burial (i.e., of the Prophet), and so it should be after the death of every imam, as many obligations of the Sharฤซสฟa depend on him.”43

Commenting on the situation in his day when the central lands of Islam, Syria, and Egypt, were under the Mamluks and the east (Persia and Transoxiana) was ravaged by Tamerlane (Tฤซmลซr Lang), Taftฤzฤnฤซย explained why there must be only one imam for all regions:

“If it is said: why is it not sufficient to appoint a ruler in every region, or why is it obligatory to appoint one who has the general authority (al-riyฤsa al-สฟฤmma)?โ€ we say: because that would lead to conflict and animosity, which would lead to the corruption of the affairs of religion as well as this world, as we witness in our ownย times.”44

He then goes on to ask, in typical dialectic style, why a conqueror like the Turks of his day (he most likely had Tamerlane in mind) could not suffice and why, therefore, there needed to be an imam. To this, he responded that such a ruler over all Muslim lands would still fulfill some of the functions but that โ€œthe matter of religion, the most important of all ends and the central pillar of all else, would be corrupted without it.โ€45

Writing about the same time in the western parts of the Islamic world, the great historian and Mฤlikฤซ juristย Ibn Khaldun (d. 808/1406) summed up the consensus succinctly:

“Appointing a leader is obligatory. Its mandatory nature is known through revealed law by the consensus of the Companions and the generation of the Followers. It is so because the Companions of the Prophet (Godโ€™s peace and blessings be upon him) hastened, upon his death, to pledge allegiance and submit consideration of their affairs to Abu Bakr (May God be pleased with him). And it was thus in every age thereafter, and the matter was established as consensus indicating the obligation of appointing a leader.”46

Ibn Khaldun then goes on to argue, in accordance with his Ashสฟari commitments, that the obligation of establishing the caliphate (like all other obligations) derives from the revealed law and not reason and hence cannot be suspended by rational judgment.

It is an understatement to note that Ibn Khaldun upheld the caliphate; he wrote his masterpiece to explain its history and advocate its return. A leading Western scholar of Islamic civilization, Hamilton Gibb, argued that the caliphate occupied a central position in Ibn Khaldunโ€™s thought. This can be inferred from the way that his chapters are logically organized to culminate in the caliphate, where he then discusses elaborately the organization associated with it before going on to analyze the causes of the stateโ€™s decay and its final destruction. It is impossible to avoid the impression that he, in addition to analyzing the evolution of political power and group solidarity, was, like other Muslim jurists of his time, concerned with the problem of reconciling the ideal demands of the Shariโ€˜a with the facts of history.47ย Others, including the Muสฟtazila, Shiสฟa, traditionalists like Ibn Taymiyya, argued that the obligation of the caliphate, like all other obligations, is known by both revelationย andย reason.48

Scholars offered numerous reasons, or rational functions, that necessitate a government. For some, these functions are the cause or part of the cause of the obligation; for others, they are its benefits, but the obligation itself stands independent of any benefits. To those who emphasized the absolute ritual necessity of the caliphate for the validity of Islamic life, such as al-Mawardi and, even more so, al-Ghazali, it was an obligation to install a caliph even if he no longer possessed effective power (shawka,ย munna) and had to depend on others (e.g., sultans) for upholding its basic functions. For others, like al-Juwayni and Ibn Taymiyya, effective power to uphold theย แธฅudลซd, maintain law and order, and defend the community and its religion was a necessary ingredient of the definition of a caliph.

Theย สฟulamฤสพย have continued to faithfully reproduce this line of reasoning until today. An eleventh-/seventeenth-century Damascene jurist notes in his authoritative compendium of Hanafi jurisprudence:

“The majorย imamaย (khilฤfa) is the right of general disposal over the people. Its investigation is inย Kalamย (i.e., theology) and establishing it is the most important of obligations. Hence, they (the Companions) gave it priority over the burial of theย Possessor ofย Miracles๏ทบ.49

Why has the caliphate been so central to Islamic creed? Chiefly, because it was the defining problem of Islamโ€”as Trinity was for Christianity. Theorizing the rightful leadership of the community was central to defining faith since the early splinter sects had called into question the mainstream communityโ€™s rectitude and fitness as the carrier and embodiment of Godโ€™s message. Justifying the rectitude of the community that preserved the Qurโ€™an and the Sunnah of the Prophetย ๏ทบย was, therefore, the central โ€˜problem spaceโ€™ within which much of Islamic thinking was formed during the first two centuries of Islam.50

The first instance of the Companionsโ€™ unanimous decision to declare political unity of the Muslims a top concern, reflected in the election of Abu Bakr, was truly consolidated in their consensus to go to war against those who had seceded from the Medinan authority. They did not merely express abstract opinions on the matter but took up arms on its basis. In doing so, they followed the Prophetโ€™s own conduct toward those who abandoned the community or tried to divide it.51ย This initial consensus of the Companions was confirmed time and again. The next clear confirmation of consensus is witnessed when สฟAli (based in Iraq) battled against Muสฟawiya (based in Syria) at แนขiffฤซn; สฟAli never entertained the idea of splitting the difference and dividing the Muslim community into two halves to avert the bloodshed, which turned out to be massive. Similarly, when สฟAbdallฤh b. al-Zubayr in Mecca confronted the Umayyads in Syria, dividing the community for the sake of peace was similarly never considered a possibility. When Ibn สฟUmar and other leading authorities refused to give allegiance to Ibn al-Zubayr, they did so precisely on this basis: the community had not united under him yet.52

The classical Sunniย สฟulamฤสพโ€™s view of the functions of the caliph is best captured in a statement attributed to Imam สฟAli. When the radicals in his army contested his right as the leader to accept arbitration in the battle against the Syrian rebels, he responded by emphasizing the necessity of a human leader to govern the affairs of the umma:

“สฟAli said, โ€œPeople must have leadership (imฤra), be it pious or impious.โ€ They asked, โ€œO Commander of the Faithful, we understand the pious, but why if it is impious?โ€ He said, โ€œBy it [legal]ย แธฅudลซdย are established, public streets are protected,ย jihฤdย is made against the enemy, and the spoils are divided.”53

If governmentย in general was a rational necessity, the caliphate was seen as the properly Islamic form of government. A helpful analogy to understand this is marriage, the pairing of males and females for companionship and reproduction: all human cultures settle on some form of this institution, adding to it constraints, ceremonies, rituals, and invocations of blessings. An Islamic marriage is not fundamentally different in terms of its basic function, but many forms of cohabitation prevalent in other traditions are prohibited and certain constraints, rituals, and legal norms added to it make of it a distinctively Islamic form of marriage.ย Ibn Taymiyya, thus, explains inย al-Siyฤsa al-sharสฟiyya:

“It must be known that the governmental authority (wilฤya) of peopleโ€™s affairs is one of the greatest obligations of religion, and, in fact, the religion cannot be established without it, for the well-being of the Children of Adam cannot be secured except by their coming together to fulfill each otherโ€™s needs. . . ย This is why all things that [God] has obligated, such asย jihฤd, justice, establishment of the pilgrimage, Friday congregations, Eid festivals, aiding the oppressed, and the establishment of Godโ€™sย แธฅudลซdย can only be established with power and authority.”54

What sets the caliphate apart from any other government is, first and foremost, formally speaking, the constitutive principle (its source, limits, ends, and functions).

The definitive classical work on the caliphate was authored by al-Mawardi, the chief judge of Baghdad andย theย leading Shฤfiสฟฤซ of his time. It gave the standard description of the caliph, namely, that a caliph is โ€œthe successor of the Prophet who protects the religion and manages and governs worldly affairs of the community by it.โ€55

Nearly all definitions mention these elements, namely, that a caliph

  1. stands in the Prophetโ€™s place, but is neither a prophet nor infallible, and commands the allegiance of the entire Muslim community, and
  2. governs the religious and worldly affairs of the Prophetโ€™s community, which effectively means that he protects the religion, defends borders, upholds law and order, and (re)distributes resources.

In other words, a caliph is defined as the leader of all followers of the Prophet Muhammadย ๏ทบย and notย primarilyย as the ruler of a territory, a country, a sect, or a chosen group of Muslimsโ€”even though he inevitably rules over and defends the territory of Muslims.56

Caliphate is not kingship

Since the earliest times, Muslims made a distinction between a properly Islamic government, which they came to callย khilฤfa, and political authority in general, which they calledย mulk. It should be noted that the wordย mulkย has dual connotations in the Arabic language: it could simply refer to any kind of political authority, one particular species of which would be the Islamic caliphate. It could also denote, pejoratively, the stereotypical kingship characterized by arbitrary power in which the ruler treats his subject and wealth as his personal property. As noted earlier, the early Muslims avoided using the termย malikย (king) for their ruler because they despised the inegalitarianism implied by this term.57ย A revealing hadith is reported in al-Bukhari, where Companion Jarir b. Abdallฤh states that a wise man from Yaman told him,

“You O Arabs will do well so long as you consult when your chief dies, for when it is taken by the sword, they become kings (mulลซk), their wrath is like the wrath of kings and their pleasure is the pleasure of kings.”58

This distinction remained operative throughout the medieval period. A Mฤlikฤซ scholarย al-Maqarrฤซย al-Tilimsฤnฤซ answered revealingly when some Sufi mendicants (fuqarฤสพ) asked him about Muslimsโ€™ misfortune with respect to their kings (mulลซk), who often act without fairness and piety. He answered,

“It is so because kingship (mulk) is not in our Law (sharสฟ); rather, it is in the law of those before us, as God mentioning His favors upon the Israelites. . . . He [God] has notย legitimizedย for us anything butย khilฤfa.”59

Al-Maqarrฤซ then goes on to identify the difference between the two as primarily relating to whether one treats authority as personal and passes it on to oneโ€™s sons dynastically. What makes the caliphate different from kingship, then, is that in the former, the interests of theย ummaย are front and center and authority is exercised as a trust.

Ibn Taymiyya is even more explicit. The obligation is not fulfilled with kingship, even if there be one just king over all Muslims, but the obligation is to install a caliph, an accountable ruler who will wield power as a trust, in the footsteps of the Prophet ๏ทบ and the early caliphs, rather than arbitrarily.

“The question arises whether kingship (mulk) is lawful and the Prophetic caliphate simply preferred or whether it is unlawful and may only be justified in the absence of the knowledge [that is it obligatory] or the power to establish the caliphate.

In our view, kingship is essentially unlawful, and the obligation is to establish a prophetic caliphate. This is because the Prophet ๏ทบ said, โ€œYou must follow my practice and the practice of the rightly guided caliphs after me; stick to it and hold fast to it. Refrain from (unjustified) innovations and remember that every (such) innovation is an errorโ€ … ย This hadith is therefore a command; it exhorts us to follow necessarily the practice of the Caliphate (of the Prophet), enjoins us to abide by it, and warns us against deviation from it. It is a command from him and definitely makes the establishment of the caliphate a duty … ย Again, the fact that the Prophet ๏ทบ expressed his dislike for the kingship that would follow the prophetic caliphate proves that kingship lacks in something that is compulsory in religion… Those who justify monarchy argue from the words of the Prophet ๏ทบ to Muสฟawiya, โ€œIf you acquire kingship, be good and kind.โ€60 But there is no (cogent) argument in this … The establishment of the caliphate is an obligatory duty, and exemption from it may be permitted only on grounds of necessity.”61

The loss

The religious necessity of the caliphate remained unquestioned untilย the twentieth century, when the arguments for abolishing the Ottoman caliphate were articulated by Turkish nationalists and made palatable, at least to the elite, by a century of secularization and Europeanization.ย A fateful moment in this transition was the seven-hour long speech by an Ottoman modernist scholar, Seyyid Bey, in the Turkish Grand National Assembly (TGNA) in 1924, in which he made the case for a Turkish republic, tragically, on Islamic grounds.62ย The Kemalistsโ€™ aggressive secularization campaign and violent de-Islamization of social life in the following decades was certainly not part of Seyyid Beyโ€™s plan, but he was not the first nor the last scholar to be used as an intellectual mercenary and then discarded by a strongman. What Atatรผrk did next, suffice it to say, inspired Hitler and Mussolini.63

The most influential theoretical defense of the abolition of the caliphate and defense of what might be calledย political secularismย came in the wake of the dissolution of the caliphate when the Azhar-trained Egyptian scholar สฟAli สฟAbd al-Raziq (1888โ€“1966) wrote hisย al-Islฤm wa-uแนฃลซl al-แธฅukmย (Islam and the Foundations of Rule, 1925). He argued that Islam is a private religion and all political actions of the Prophet ๏ทบ and his successors (that is, the caliphs) were accidental and conceptually separate from Islam as a religion. สฟAbd al-Raziq had spent two years at Oxford when his education was cut short by WWI, and his family had played a founding role in the Liberal Constitutionalist Party (แธคizb al-Aแธฅrฤr al-Dustลซriyyฤซn, a breakaway from the Wafd, which was a secular nationalist anticolonial party; theย แธคizb al-Aแธฅrฤrย had an even more secular agenda as it advocated the emulation of Western countries). สฟAli สฟAbd al-Raziq himself was a politician and had run, unsuccessfully, for a seat in the Parliamentary elections of 1923-24 on the partyโ€™s ticket.64ย He wrote, in short, as a politician with a clear agenda, not merely a scholar, although posterity has misread his work as a heroic heresy with mystical depth. His book betrays a forced, ahistorical reading of both the Prophetโ€™s mission and the succeeding caliphs and an equally shallow understanding of modernity. The Azhari establishment condemned the book and formally defrocked its author, and the leading scholars of the Muslim world authored numerous detailed refutations.65ย In fact, สฟAli สฟAbd al-Raziqโ€™s controversial book ended up focusing the attention of the leading scholars of the twentieth century on this question, furnishing, in defense of the caliphate, the closest example in the modern period of a renewed consensus of leading Islamic authorities across the world. The power of an argument, however, often lies not in its theoretical cogency but in its timeliness. The Arab nationalists and secularists could not have asked for a better way to boost their agenda.

Did the Prophet ๏ทบ establish a state?

สฟAli สฟAbd al-Raziqโ€™s case was based on the argument that the Prophetโ€™s ๏ทบ message was religious and spiritual, not political. He offered as evidence the claim that the Qurโ€™an never commanded the caliphate, nor did the Sunna.66ย He must have known that the Qurโ€™an not mentioning or naming a thing is barely an argument for its non-obligation or non-validity. After all, the Qurโ€™an does not give the number of the daily prayers, nor specify the geographic coordinates of the city in which the Prophet of Islam ๏ทบ was born, nor that in which he is buried, etc.; these are known only through the transmission of such knowledge through the Companions and the succeeding generations. The Qurโ€™an, the scholars had generally argued, mentions the direct and indirect obligation for the believing community (referred to in the Qurโ€™an as theย believersย or theย umma) to be united under a ruler from among them and contains numerousย constitutional,ย political, andย legalย commandmentsโ€”rules that can only be implemented in an autonomous Islamic polity. The signification of direct commands like 4:59 (โ€œObey … those in authority among youโ€)67ย was consolidated by innumerable indirect commands and references. For instance,

  1. the imperative to be a distinct community whose members were forbidden to make compromising alliances with outsiders;
  2. the command to make war, peace, and political treaties as a sovereign community;
  3. obeying no other law but Godโ€™s, hence requiring the community to be legally sovereign;
  4. upholding the Law in all areas of collective life, including the penal code, marital and social life, commercial and financial regulations, and so on; and finally,
  5. a distinct โ€œforeign policyโ€ as the Prophet ๏ทบ dispatched epistles to the neighboring sovereigns and emperors (which implied the obligation on his successors to follow up on them), in addition to his punitive campaigns against claimants of prophecy like แนฌalแธฅa, Musaylima, and other tribes that acted treacherously and rebelliously after entering Islam,68ย and his command to prepare a punitive campaign on the Roman border just before his return to his Lord, and so on.

All of these factors required, beyond doubt, that the followers of the Prophet ๏ทบ form a sovereign political community and control, if not monopolize, the means of violence. The aforementioned are historically undisputed facts that indicate that his successors merely obeyed his commands and continued his policies. From a historical perspective, had the Companions and then the Umayyads not continued the Prophetโ€™s political and military activism, Islam would have been little more than forgotten tribal lore in history.

The Sunnah has been far more explicit on the question of successorship. Numerous hadiths command obedience to those who succeeded the Prophet ๏ทบ as mentioned in Ibn Taymiyyaโ€™s quote above. In fact, สฟAli สฟAbd al-Raziq seems to have been unaware that the leadingย สฟulamฤสพย had addressed his concerns at great length. Al-Juwayni, being an Ashสฟarite who did not accept unitary hadiths (ฤแธฅฤd) as grounds for certitude, limiting definitive knowledge to multiple concurrent (mutawฤtir) reports alone, had written his aforementioned work explicitly to furnish an incontrovertible proof for the necessity of the caliphate. In contrast, Ibn Taymiyya, who emphatically argued for the possibility of certitude based on less-than-concurrent reports and for the efficacy of reason in establishing religious obligation, did not shy away from using numerous sound hadiths in establishing the same while also appealing to consensus and rational arguments.69

สฟAbd al-Raziqโ€™s crucial error, however, was conceptual: he seems to have picked up the modern religion-versus-politics dichotomy during his sojourn in Europe and, unaware that these were recently constructed categories foreign to Islam and perturbed by the autocratic tendencies of the rulers who used religion to prop up their decadence, applied them to Islamic theology and history. To anyone not schooled in western secularism, it would seem arbitrary and unjustifiable to declare certain Qurโ€™anic and Sunnaic commandments โ€˜religiousโ€™ and others โ€˜secular.โ€™

What gaveสฟAbd al-Raziqโ€™s attack its potency was that he knew the stakes well: he not only undermined the aforementioned scriptural evidence and traditional discourse on the subject, but went for the jugular by attacking Abu Bakr and the rest of the Companions for theย riddaย wars that were the first step in consolidating the Medinan political authority in Arabia. According to สฟAbd al-Raziq, they had essentially agreed, willingly or unwillingly, with Abu Bakr to engage in a worldly war in the name of religion against perfectly good Muslim tribes who merely resisted Medinan authority.70ย Wittingly or not, สฟAbd al-Raziq was willing to discard not only consensus but also the integrity of the closest Companions around the Final Messenger of God, the same men whose integrity is assured in the Qurโ€™an, and indeed, the integrity of whose consensus is the only guarantee of the preservation of the Qurโ€™an itself. Together, this coupling forms the very foundation of Islam.

Longing for the caliphate

To appreciate how deeply Muslims have felt the ideal of continuity and unity embodied in the caliphate, it helps to get a glimpse of how the loss of and rupture in the caliphate have been historically experienced at not only political but also emotional and cultural levels. Islamic studies scholar Mona Hassan has richly chronicled this experience in the wake of the Mongol sacking of Baghdad in 656/1258 and then again some seven centuries later in 1924.71

Numerous Islamic scholars, activists, and transnational movements have kept alive the idea of a union of Muslims over the past century.ย Whereas most such groups consider a reconstituted caliphate a by-product of their revivalist and reformist activities, a few such movements have made it their primary objective. For groups most directly dedicated to resurrecting the caliphate like แธคizb al-Taแธฅrฤซr (The Liberation Party) of Palestinian-Jordanian and Tanzeem-e-Islami (The Islamic Organization) of South Asian provenance, now both international, caliphate is not only a fruit of collaboration among reformed Muslim societies and states but the political end of the struggle as well as the instrument of attaining a desirable state of affairs and warding off internal and foreign threats to Muslims.72ย Over the course of the twentieth century, ambitious political leaders of Muslim states have worked to create links and institutions at the international level to inch toward greater pan-Islamic collaboration. In the post-WWII era of developmentalist policies, nation-state politics largely trumped any serious attempts.73ย Today, such aspirations have resurfaced once again.74ย Non-state actors, like the ones mentioned earlier, have been more successful in keeping the idea alive. The most significant ones have been the socio-religious reformist organizations like the Muslim Brotherhood (in Arabic speaking countries) and Jamaat-e Islami (in South Asia) that have sought to restore the caliphate only as a distant goal, never making it their priority.ย Only in times of crisis, such as the Israeli occupation of Palestine, would the pan-Islamic sentiment find a vent. In the era of statism (1940sโ€“80s), the Islamic movements mobilized the masses to take the helms of various states. They often failed, and where they succeeded, as in Iran and Sudan, they often discovered that the internal, secularizing logic of the nation-state model was far stronger than their own ideological aspirations and often succumbed to repression, corruption, and self-serving regional and geopolitical concerns. Statehood never seriously took root in the Muslim world, and whereas socially, Islamism became increasingly popular, it never fulfilled its promise. The idea of the caliphate remained on the backburner as the ultimate goal that had to be realized as the final step after the attainment of democracy and progress.75

The present: Failing states

The Arab Revolt (1916โ€“1918) began a century and God-knows-how-much-longer era of political illegitimacy and instability in the Arab Middle East. Today, the region is increasingly convulsive. One contemporary historian notes, linking the fall of the Ottoman Caliphate to the malaise in the contemporary Middle East,

“I think everyone is rational to be pessimistic about the prospects for the region. None of these problems have a short-term solution.”76

Similarly, in his aptly titledย A Peace to End All Peaceย (1989), historian David Fromkin wrote, reflecting on the continuing legacy of the European partitioning of the region:

“Continuing local opposition, whether on religious grounds or others, to the settlement of 1922 or to the fundamental assumptions upon which it was based, explains the characteristic feature of the region’s politics: that in the Middle East there is no sense of legitimacyโ€”no agreement on rules of the gameโ€”and no belief, universally shared in the region, that within whatever boundaries, the entities that call themselves countries or the men who claim to be rulers are entitled to recognition as such. In that sense, successors to the Ottoman sultans have not yet been permanently installed.”77

Today, the future of Muslim nation-states is less certain than it has ever been over the last century. At least one reason for the unlikelinessโ€”and, in the words of one scholar, theย impossibilityโ€”of the nation-state is ideological: Islam.78ย That is, given the deep roots of Islam in these societies, alternative attempts at constructing legitimacy through secularโ€”whether nationalist, regional, leftist-internationalist, or otherโ€”narratives have failed. As the Arab scholar Nazih Ayubi described it in his influential studyย Overstating the Arab Stateย (1996), twentieth-century post-colonial Arab states are not strong but fierceโ€”meaning, they are weak, illegitimate, and hence ferocious.79ย Because they do not command peopleโ€™s broad allegiance (but only that of the elite benefitting from them), they can only assert control through brute force, often combined with and legitimated through extraneous factors such as regional threats and animosities (e.g., Israel, Zionists, crusaders, Shiสฟa, Sunnis, etc.) and the exploitation of religious and ethnic divisions. As the elite realized the failure of their secular programs, especially with the failure of Nasser-led Arab nationalism and the epic humiliation of the Arab armies at the hands of Israel in 1967, they hoped to exploit Islam more effectively. The results have been unimpressive for a number of reasons.

First, although the rulers could control some of the สฟulamฤสพ and religious institutions, Sunni Islam has never been amenable to a clerical hierarchy, and such attempts invariably engender or strengthen alternative, competing claims of religious authority. An example is the Egyptian stateโ€™s attempt to control the ancient al-Azhar University. Islam being a strongly scripturalist religion, the spread of literacy only facilitates the availability of its anti-authoritarian, if not anti-clerical, message to all believers. The same spirit of Islam that had thwarted the absolutist ambitions of the Umayyad (in the form of rebellions) and then the Abbasid caliphs (in the form of the heroic resistance of Imam Ahmad b. Hanbal) refuses to be manipulated by the military autocrats and monarchs of today. Another, and perhaps the most important, ideological factor obstructing Islamโ€™s recruitment in the nation-building project is the global nature of the Islamic community and the essentially territorial nature of the modern state.

This illegitimacy of the state in Muslim-majority regions has had devastating consequences. Terrorism has been a direct and unavoidable consequence. These insecure, weak, and fierce states inevitably govern through repression and turn religious and cultural authorities into mercenaries against their own societies. Weaponing globalism for their cause, the autocrats hire global mercenary โ€œสฟulamฤสพโ€ against socially invested scholars. The oppressed inevitably look to the international community, which seldom helps except when moved by its own interests. This further deepens the illegitimacy of the state on the one hand and the distrust of any would-be reformers (who now can be labeled by the autocrats as foreign agents) on the other.

The secular theology of the modern state

These problems are not accidental but essential to any state that has to contend with a popular religion that it cannot re-create for its own purposes. In addition, Islam is conceptually unique in its ability to challenge modernity not only theologically but also politically through its own compelling notions of belonging, solidarity, rule-of-law, and tolerance for plurality. Aspects of this Islamic exceptionalism have been recognized by both scholars who study the tradition as well as those who investigate the lived experience.80

No nation-state can do without demanding near-total loyalty to the state and exclusion of outside interests and influences. It makes and implements laws and makes life-and-death decisions, drafting citizens to kill and die for its interests. In a liberal democracy with an impartial judiciary, this demand is presumably not arbitrary and the powers of the state are checked, but this is rarely the case in reality. Liberal democracies have shown themselves to be helpless before predatory capitalism and incompatible with religious commitment, community ethics, and now ecological sustainability. Lacking any collective and transcendent moral ideals, citizens in the modern state are either manipulated by large, multinational corporations or ethno-nationalist demagogues, or both. Liberal democratic or not, the modern state effectively functions as the absolute arbiter of the law, ethics, and lives of its citizens.

The modern nation-state, precisely defined, is an institution foreign to Islam in any of its recognizable forms. Commonplace knowledge to the scholars of Islamic tradition and history, this incompatibility has been powerfully argued recently by Wael Hallaqโ€™s important bookย The Impossible State. He contends that the modern nation-state is an amoral, if not immoral, institution, and an unsuitable home to Islam. His case, however, is based on a particular notion of the โ€˜state,โ€™ and this has caused much confusion among non-specialists. A digression to clarify this claim, therefore, is in order.

Whether and when we can use the term โ€˜stateโ€™ to describe the early Islamic forms of government depends on how we settle the thorny question of the definition of the state. The modern state has so ubiquitously conquered the contemporary world and imagination as to threaten all historical understanding and along with that, any historically extended and authentic alternative. European intellectual historians generally agree that the concept of the state emerged in Europe between 1300 and 1600 due to a number of specific developments.81ย What set it apart from any prior form of rule is the confluence of a number of conceptions that constructed the state as โ€œan omnipotent yet impersonal powerโ€: (a) the state as a separate legal and constitutional order that governs, abstracted and distinct from the monarch or the officials who hold office, (b) the state as the sole source of law, exclusive of God, the Church, or the Holy Roman Empire, within its own territory, and (c) the state as the sole appropriate object of its citizensโ€™ allegiance.82ย Secularity, territoriality, abstraction (i.e., impersonality), and sovereignty are thus held to be the necessary ingredients of the modern state. Thisย maximalistย definition of the state employed by historians is to be contrasted with the more widely employedย minimalistย definitions, such as the one offered by Charles Tilly, who sees states as โ€œcoercion-wielding organizations that are distinct from households and kinship groups and exercise clear priority in some respects over all other organizations within substantial territories.โ€83ย The Medinan order certainly represented such a โ€˜stateโ€™ by the time the Prophet ๏ทบ passed away, one that was further consolidated by the end of Abu Bakrโ€™s reign. This latter use of the term, however, is too imprecise to be meaningful, and, following Hallaq, we are better off using the term โ€˜governmentโ€™ or, better yet, โ€˜governanceโ€™ rather than โ€˜stateโ€™ to capture the essence of premodern Islamic forms of political authority.

Strictly speaking, the modern state is an abstract, impersonal institution apart from any particular individuals or dynasties that hold its reigns. Being a seventeenth-century European development, it is a new species of power foreign to Islamic theology or jurisprudence. Political philosophers and historians have long suggested that as an institution, it assumes the powers that belonged to God in traditional Christianity. To quote Carl Schmitt in his essay โ€œPolitical Theology,โ€ perhaps the most quoted words in modern political theory:

“All significant concepts of the modern theory of the state are secularized theological concepts not only because of their historical developmentโ€”in which they were transferred from [Christian] theology to the theory of the state, whereby, for example, the omnipotent God became the omnipotent lawgiverโ€”but also because of their systematic structure, the recognition of which is necessary for a sociological consideration of these concepts.”84

The obvious thing to note in this observation is that the theological origins and pretensions of political concepts define the modern state: sovereignty (a god-like, unquestionable authority to make laws and decide exceptions to them), territory (a bounded area where the sovereignty of the state is supreme), national community (the believers in the nationโ€™s greatness and mythic past), and citizenship (rights given to individuals on the basis of relation to the state, denied to non-citizens),85ย and so on. But its greater insight, I think, is to point out the ideologically secular structure of the state; it is not an empty space to be filled by whatever ideology, but possesses one of its own. This is what Wael Hallaq alludes to in the following passage:

“Modern Islamist discourses assume the modern state to be a neutral tool of governance, one that can be harnessed to perform certain functions according to the choices and dictates of its leaders. [It can be turned into] โ€ฆ an Islamic state implementing the values and ideals enshrined in the Qurโ€™an and those that the Prophet had once realized in his โ€œmini-stateโ€ of Medina. … [This is not so.] Itย inherentlyย [emphasis in the original] produces certain distinctive effects that are political, social, economic, cultural, epistemic, and, no less, psychological, which is to say that the state fashions particular knowledge systems that in turn determine and shape the landscape of individual and collective subjectivity and thus much of the meaning of its subjectsโ€™ lives.”86

One of the reasons for this ideological power of the state is that the state is its own lawgiver, judge, and executioner. This awesome and total power devolves to a seemingly immaterial, abstract entity but, in reality, is always wielded by some group of men. Furthermore, these authorities of the modern state are enforced (of course, always selectively) by global powers in the name of the international agreement that is the nation-state system. When the powers of this leviathan were found too absolute, the ideas of institutional checks and balances and the separation of powers inscribed in a constitution and democratic processes were born. Yet, all these checks and balances reside within the state. In imperfect democracies (are there any perfect ones?), the totality of this power becomes clearer, and the separation of powers becomes often less than effective. But, as numerous legal historians have argued, the separation-of-powers hypothesis does not hold in reality in even the most institutionally developed nation-states like the United States.87 When the state acts as a unified actor, as in times of real or fabricated crises, wars, and triumphsโ€”which are potentially continual or even constantโ€”it acts as an absolute power, a โ€œmortal god,โ€ as the Leviathan, a mythic creature of unlimited powerโ€”as imagined by the English philosopher Thomas Hobbes.

The insurmountable trouble for Islamic theology is not that the rulers as individuals may go rogue or engage in war, enact discriminatory policies, and arbitrary executions, which are all comprehensible evils and inevitable realities in political life. Religious authorities have always felt free to invoke Islamic norms to critique and censure the rulers, at times even justifying armed rebellion. Rather, the โ€œimpossibilityโ€ of the modern state within an Islamic framework, as argued by Hallaq and others, is that the state is, by definition as well as structurally, supreme. Religious opinions and institutions are authorized by the state, not the other way around. Even if the state elite are โ€œMuslimโ€ or โ€œIslamic,โ€ these scholars argue, structurally the modern state cannot be Islamic; it is secularย andย secularizing. And yet, being secular has never stopped the state elite anywhere, including in Europe and America, from exploiting religion to further their ends. The idea of an Islamic state, therefore, is an oxymoron, and the experiences of the actual states that have claimed to be Islamic over the last several decades only confirm this.

Another, and even more concrete, incommensurability with the demands of the modern stateโ€™s territorial sovereignty is that Islam brooks no differentiation of rights and duties of Muslims based on regional or territorial affiliation. Numerous scriptural commandments of solidarity and mutual support make it impossible to cut off Muslims in one region from the needs, rights, wealth, and suffering of other Muslims, except on temporary and pragmatic grounds.ย To act in response to the oppression of the Rohingya, the Uyghurs, the Palestinians, and the Kashmiris is, therefore, a direct Qurโ€™anic command to all Muslims, a command whose enactment is subject only to considerations of distance and feasibility.ย A political structuration that circumscribes the loyalties of individualsย to the territorial boundaries of the stateย is in essential conflict with Islam. Even more problematic to the demands of a territorial state is its citizensโ€™ allegiance to a religious authority emanating from outside its borders. The widespread scholarly, intellectual, and Sufi networks that have defined the lands of Islam in the past continue to pose a challenge to the demands of the nation-state. Of course, limited municipal or administrative independence of territorial or regional governments is indeed possible (and desirable), but the sovereignty claimed by the nation-state goes far beyond this. It is, therefore, crucial to distinguish the state, an abstract and sovereign entity, fromย government, the name for the administrative and legal apparatus in a region. Accordingly, the imagination of a future caliphate must not be deluded into thinking that local governments, institutions, communities, and histories must be destroyed to create a regional superstate.

Many other critiques of the nation-state can be made, and indeed have been made, but our purpose is not to offer a comprehensive critique but to present some reasons for why the nation-state has had such a deeply troubled career in the lands of Islam, and why the end of the nation-state may offer a historical opportunity for the reconstitution of a more Islamic and humane form of political existence for Muslims.

Looking ahead

“The ideas of economists and political philosophers, both when they are right and when they are wrong, are more powerful than is commonly understood: Indeed, the world is run by little else.”88

The critiques of the modern state that I have proposed in the foregoing require that the future caliphate be envisioned not as a super-nation-state, or merely a merger of existing states, but as a different kind of governance that draws its legitimacy from a different political philosophy than the one grounded in Westphalia, nationalism, and secularism. This does not require turning away from modern experience to a prefabricated premodern model, but rather seeking wisdom and guidance from the past while looking to the future, broadening the scope of thinking, and engaging the contemporary experience beyond hegemonic categories. Once we disabuse ourselves of the notion that the nation-state is a given (until foreign masters and textbooks permit us to think otherwise), many inspirations from past and present open up.

The notion of an innovative restoration of the caliphate is far from unthinkable; it was how many independent Muslim thinkers imagined the future. The influential Egyptian jurist สฟAbd al-Razzฤq al-Sanhลซrฤซ (1895-1971), who is also the single most important author of Egyptian, Iraqi, and other Arab civil laws, shared an unambiguous commitment to the revival of the caliphate in a systematic and progressive manner:

“Given that establishing a rightly-guided or complete caliphate is impossible under the current conditions, there is no alternative to establishing incomplete or deficient Islamic government (แธฅukลซma) on the basis of necessity that the current circumstances impose upon the Islamic world today. But such a system (niแบ“ฤm) must be considered deficient and temporary โ€ฆ The ideal caliphate system of the future must be flexible, for as we have seen, theย sharฤซสฟaย does not impose a specific [administrative] form for governance atย all.”89

He goes on to offer these broad requirements for a feasible and effective caliphate:

  1. Unification of the Islamic world;
  2. application of Islamic law, and
  3. certain religious and political features. These he further elaborates as follows:
  1. Separation of powers: as history and experience show that concentration of power in the hand of one person or body leads to the domination of the political over the religious and moral.
  2. Legal reform: the traditional Islamic legal system (outside of ritual and religious aspects) had led to stagnation, which makes it necessary to engage in serious research and effect an intellectual renaissance of sorts before applying it in practice.
  3. Decentralization and localism: history and experience show that the unity of the Islamic world cannot be maintained stably in a highly centralized state, nor is that desirable from the perspective of Islamic jurisprudence; any such attempt will have to be decentralized with a large measure of freedom givenย to each region to govern itself.90

Sanhลซrฤซ was no mere dreamer; his subsequent studies detailed at length the kinds of issues that would have to be faced in such a multilayered government, down to the kinds of committees for various religious and other affairs and the sensitivity to the rights of non-Muslims as well neighboring non-Muslim statesโ€”โ€œthe nations of the eastโ€โ€”that would be required.

In this vein, the United Statesโ€™ constitutional architecture represents one of the best cases of political envisioning the modern world has seen, and no contemporary effort of political thinking can afford to ignore it. Right-wing pundit George Will recently remarked in an interview for his bookย The Conservative Sensibilityย that the Bush administrationโ€™s attempt to bring democracy to Iraq failed because Iraq did not have men like John Locke the philosopher, George Washington the statesman, Alexander Hamilton the visionary economist, and the society of eighteenth-century America. His larger argument is that certain political geniuses created the American political system, which in turn created a culture and subjectivity, which is necessary for a successful democracy. In other words, one needs each of these three elements for a successful political vision: a set of shared ideals, an exceptional and courageous set of visionary thinkers, and a society ready to respond to their vision. George Will is hardly an expert on Iraq, and his view of America myopically filters out all the blood and contingency from its history, but some of his insights are correct: the need for visionaries and for buy-in from society and, in particular, the failure of imported solutions. Even more noteworthy is Willโ€™s observation about the American Declaration of Independence: it sees its purpose as not inventing rights to be imposed top-down, butย securingย pre-existing rights widely believed to be given by God.91

We imagine the caliphate as a federation of local governments that may be governed democratically or by any number of traditional or yet undiscovered institutionalization ofย shuraโ€”by which I meanย representation, consultation, and accountability. Islamic Law has been inherently legally pluralistic and does not seek to impose its communal norms on non-Muslims. This is so because the Islamic notion of communal life and governance is essentially bottom-up: people can be governed only by laws they believe in. Another related commitment of Islamic governance is the integrity of family and community. A third related commitment of Islamic tradition as it historically developed has been small government and respect for local customs. When modernizing nation-states abandoned these standards and tried to force Islamic law into a state law, disastrous abuse ensued.92

All these commitments provide building blocks for a constitutional design that will need to balance the check on the powers of the government. The institutional design of any future confederation of Muslim governments, in short, will have to use the ancient resources of Islamic tradition, but equally important will be the adoption of compatible contemporary institutions.

This is not a call for a violent revolution, for it inevitably summons a reign of terror in its wake. It is a call, rather, for new discourses and practices in the framework of the broad, shared framework of the caliphate that take the collective future of the global Muslim ummaย seriously.

It is a call for Muslims to allow ourselves to dream big without neglecting small, immediate obligations and duties, to think globally even as we must act locally. It is a call for conversations, networking, rethinking, and reimagining the possibilities of living politically as Muslims. It is a call for young Muslims everywhere to link up with each other across artificial borders and ask themselves practical, moral questions:ย how can we respond better to the loss of faith and devotion to God, the apathy and corruption of the elite, lift up the dispossessed refugees, aid our persecuted brethren in faith, facilitate economic collaboration, alter political institutions, improve religious discourse, enrich dialogue and discourse with Muslims within and across sectarian and national boundaries, and improve education and communication across the many barriers of distance, language, and prejudice?ย 

ย All these questions must be answered in a way that simultaneously defeats the autocrats as well as the terrorists, not only in their respective ideologies but in their tactics and worldviews.

When ISIS activities were at their peak and the western media were competing in publishing the most sensationalist stories about chopped heads and murderous suicides, as a researcher working on the issue at the time, I wanted to go beyond the headlines and get a personal grip on what ISIS was really about. Skeptical as I was about the pornography of violence that the group produced specifically for the Western media, I looked in their publications (such as the glossy magazine,ย Dabiq) for clues of the culture beyond the pervasive violence and judgments of unbelief. Nothing helped me understand it better than the obscure and largely ignored reports about the conduct of its members and supporters regarding how they treated each other. There were numerous clues that created a picture: Western, European, white recruits were treated as superior, they were given leading positions from where they controlled the messaging and even the direction, and recruits from poorer, darker countries were routinely humiliated and marginalized. The children were taught violence and hatred from the get-go, rather than knowledge, reasoning, and compassion. There was the cherry-picked invocation of legal norms from classical manuals, but no attention to history, context, and diversity; their apocalyptic message was the antithesis of these virtues so essential to Islamic tradition. I knew that these features could not be made up by the CIA propagandists, and they revealed the core. In a field rife with enormous propaganda and conspiracy theories, down-to-earth data like this helped me understand this bunch of angry thugs and psychopaths, theย mariqaย and theย khawarijย as prophesied and condemned by the Beloved Prophet ๏ทบ as โ€œyoung fools who read the Qurโ€™an but it does not go past their throats.โ€93

The pursuit of a just political order cannot replace the pursuit of humble prayers, reverence for parents, better marriages, deeper friendships, robust local communities, and most of all concern for justice for the underprivileged and the weak.

Maintaining the status quo in the Muslim world is a pipe-dream; the dream to change it is not. The current order is un-Islamic, unethical, and inimical to a decent future for Muslims and our human brethren at large. Those who wish to maintain it are a small and shrinking elite. To maintain these despotic states, these elites are having not only to suppress their majorities and kill or silence every last possibility of independent, moral thinking but also denature and distort Islam and massively brainwash Muslim societies. These grotesquely repressive and nearly-failed states are different from ISIS only in superficial ways. They are actively engaged in eliminating and replacing the Muslim sense of solidarity, as well as narrowing theological, jurisprudential, and ethical discourse to serve exclusively their interests.

We Muslims, I submit, must reimagine the caliphate as a confederation of governments in the core regions of Islam that protects a range of human rights for all, provides political and economic stability to these regions, and allows Muslims to develop a variety of local political arrangements while embracing the larger religious and cultural unity of these regions. Such an order would not only be in accordance with the divine command but also is the only long term alternative to the mutually reinforcing coterie of despots and terrorists.

Notes

  1. Diyar Guldogan, โ€œTurkish Republic continuation of Ottoman Empire,โ€ Anadolu Agency, 10 Oct 18,ย http://aa.com.tr/en/todays-headlines/turkish-republic-continuation-of-ottoman-empire/1059924ย (Accessed 19 Dec 2018). See also, Rashid Dar, โ€œThe Other C-word: Caliphate,โ€ย http://ciceromagazine.com/features/the-other-c-word-caliphate/
  2. Azadeh Moaveni, โ€œThe Lingering Dream of an Islamic State,โ€ย New York Times, 12 Jan 2018.
  3. Ibid.
  4. This observationย was made by the Jewish-American constitutional scholar at Harvard University, Noah Feldman, in hisย The Fall and Rise of the Islamic Stateย (Princeton University Press, 2008), 1.
  5. John Keane,ย The Life and Death of Democracyย (W. W. Norton & Company, 2009): โ€œThe new democracy was a bastard. Its creation was unintended. Its survival was at no point in time guaranteed. It was not inevitableโ€ (161).
  6. Sheldon S. Wolin and Nicholas Xenos (eds.),ย Fugitive Democracy and Other Essaysย (Princeton University Press, 2016).
  7. This statement appears almost verbatim five times in the Qurโ€™an, see, e.g., 2:216.
  8. This is a small sample of such reports, notwithstanding the wishful exaggerations of western journalists: โ€œDespots are pushing the Arab world to become more secular,โ€ย The Economist, 2 Nov 2017,ย https://www.economist.com/middle-east-and-africa/2017/11/02/despots-are-pushing-the-arab-world-to-become-more-secular; โ€œThe Arab world in seven charts: Are Arabs turning their backs on religion?โ€ 24 Jun 2019,ย https://www.bbc.com/news/world-middle-east-48703377.
  9. Samuel P. Huntington,ย The Clash of Civilizations and the Remaking of World Order.(Touchstone, 1993/1996).
  10. Benjamin R. Barber,ย Jihad Vs. McWorldย (Ballantine Books, 1996).
  11. John Gray, John,ย Endgames: Questions in Late Modern Political Thoughtย (Polity Press, 1997).
  12. Stephen D. Krasner,ย Sovereignty: Organized Hypocrisyย (Princeton University Press, 1999).
  13. For instance, Kenichi Ohmae,ย The End of the Nation-State: The Rise of Regional Economiesย (Free Press, 1995); Luigi Padula,ย End of the Nation-State: A Historical Perspectiveย (2015).
  14. Peter Dockrill,ย Business Insider, 6/26,ย https://www.businessinsider.com/climate-apartheid-united-nations-report-2019-6ย (Accessed 7/4/19).)
  15. This argument has been made in Wael B. Hallaq,ย The Impossible State: Islam, Politics, and Modernityโ€™s Moral Predicamentย (Columbia University Press, 2012); here Hallaq argues that the modern state is not a neutral arrangement that can be transformed at will, as Islamic reformers had initially thought, but one that is essentially amoral and incompatible with any historically recognizable form of Islam. Andrew F. March, in his more recentย The Caliphate of Man: Popular Sovereignty in Modern Islamic Thoughtย (Harvard University Press, 2019), tells the story of the failure of attempts to Islamize the state in the twentieth century, and points to reasons that confirm Hallaqโ€™s thesis: โ€œIt is a short step from the prerevolutionary ideological claim that โ€˜the state must be run by the sacred lawโ€™ to โ€˜whatever the state requires for its defense, preservation, and welfare is what the sacred law isโ€™โ€ (225).
  16. Salman Sayyid,ย Recalling the Caliphateย (Hurst &ย Co. 2014), 190โ€“911.
  17. Richard A. Shweder, โ€œGeertzโ€™s Challenge: Is It Possible to Be a Robust Cultural Pluralist and a Dedicated Political Liberal at the Same Time?,โ€ in Austin Sarat, Lawrence Douglas, and Martha Merrill Umphrey (eds.),ย Law without Nationsย (Stanford Law Books, 2010), 226.
  18. Columbia University Press, 2018.
  19. Arjun Appaduri, โ€œAcross the World, Genocidal States Are Attacking Muslims. Is Islam Really Their Target?,โ€ย Scroll.in, 22 May 2018,ย https://scroll.in/article/879591/from-israel-to-myanmar-genocidal-projects-are-less-about-religion-and-more-about-predatory-statesย (Accessed 29 May 2018).
  20. The โ€œWar on Terror,โ€ admittedly, has also been successful in making willing subjects out of Muslims. Thus, Sayyid,ย Recalling the Caliphate, 189-90: โ€œMuslims have been the most visible targets of the War on Terror; they have been conscripted into an emerging political consciousness, by the never-ending war. They trade stories comedic (โ€˜flying while been Muslimโ€™), horrific (the visceral sadism in the force-feeding of the hunger strikers in Guantanamo) and heroic (daily grind of living under occupations in Palestine, Kashmir, Chechnya, and Burma). The conversations of the ummahย are now irredeemably coloured by the War on Terror as Kemalists and Islamists adjust to the banality of its execution.โ€ Many thanks to Mohammed El-Sayed Bushra for this reference.
  21. Times of Israel, 9 July 2019,ย https://www.timesofisrael.com/liberman-future-peace-deal-with-palestinians-must-include-arab-israelis/
  22. This hadith is reported through two companions, Thawbฤn (Abu Dawลซd # 4297) and Abลซ Hurayra, (Musnadย Aแธฅmad), and regarded as sound.
  23. Foreign Affairs, Summer 1993, 72.3.
  24. Azad Essa, โ€œMuslims being ‘erased’ from Central African Republic,โ€ย Aljazeera, 31 Jul 2015,ย https://www.aljazeera.com/news/2015/07/amnesty-muslims-erased-central-african-republic-150731083248166.htmlย (Accessed 19 Dec 2018).
  25. Yale University Press, 2017.
  26. David Wasserstein, โ€œHow Islam Saved the Jews,โ€ย https://kavvanah.wordpress.com/2012/06/04/how-islam-saved-the-jews-david-wasserstein/ย (Accessed 7/4/19).)
  27. Muslim # 1342.
  28. For the Orientalist literature, the confusion has been spread since Patricia Crone and Martin Hinds,ย Godโ€™s Caliphย (1986). For contemporary Muslim literature, an endless stream of literature is being generated that describes humans as Godโ€™s vicegerents. Its earliest case may have been Abu al-Aสฟla al-Mawdudiโ€™s popular Urdu exegesis of the Qurโ€™an,ย Tafhim al-Qurโ€™an.
  29. For a study of this phenomenon, see Andrew F. March,ย The Caliphate of Man: Popular Sovereignty in Modern Islamic Thoughtย (Harvard Universityย Press, 2019).
  30. See the comparison chart in David Graeber,ย Debt: The First 5000 Yearsย (2014), 272.
  31. Noah Feldman,ย Fall and Rise of the Islamic Stateย (2008), xxxix.
  32. Hรผseyin Yฤฑlmaz,ย Caliphate Redefined: The Mystical Turn in the Ottoman Political Thoughtย (Princeton University Press, 2018).
  33. For more on the millet system, see Tesneem Alkiek, โ€œTolerance, Minorities, and Ideological Perspectives,โ€ย https://yaqeeninstitute.org/tesneem-alkiek/tolerance-minorities-and-ideological-perspectives/
  34. Wadad Kadi and Aram Shahin, โ€œcaliph, caliphate,โ€ inย Princeton Encyclopedia of Islamic Political Thought, 85.
  35. Even though belief in (as a result of the dispute about the appointment of) the right imam was the defining problem for the Shiสฟa, the list of the five well-known beliefs for the Imami Shiสฟa did not become settled until the fifth/eleventh century; see Mohammed Ali Amir-Moezzi, โ€œEarly Shฤซสฟฤซ Theology,โ€ inย The Oxford Handbook of Islamic Theology, 82-3.
  36. Patricia Crone, โ€œIbadis,โ€ in G. Bowering (ed.),ย Princeton Encyclopedia of Islamic Political Thoughtย (Princeton University Press, 2013), 230.
  37. For a study of al-Juwayniโ€™s political thought, see my article โ€œPolitical Metaphors and Concepts in the Writings of an Eleventh-Century Sunni Scholar, Abลซ al-Maสฟฤlฤซ al-Juwaynฤซ,โ€ย Journal of the Royal Asiatic Society, 26.1-2 (2016): 7-18. For an overview of the entire classical period and Ibn Taymiyyaโ€™s innovative political ideas, see my monographย Politics, Law, and Community in Islamic Thought: The Taymiyyan Momentย (Cambridge University Press, 2012).
  38. After a clear text in the Qurโ€™an or a multiple corroborated (mutawฤtir) hadith, that is. Al-Juwaynฤซ, Ghiyฤthฤซ, 39-43.
  39. Yฤฑlmaz,ย Caliphate Redefined.
  40. Ibn แธคazm,ย al-Fiแนฃal fฤซ al-milal wa-l-ahwฤโ€™ wa-l-niแธฅal, 4:87.
  41. The Muสฟtazila and the Kharijites generally uphold the obligation; only a handful of Muสฟtazila, such as Hishฤm al-Fuwฤtฤซ, who argued that no caliphate can be established in civil war, thus denying สฟAliโ€™s caliphate. The Najadฤt were short-lived fanatic Kharijites who excommunicated all other Muslims, and who in reality always had an imam, but denied the obligation of having one.
  42. The wording inย แนขaแธฅฤซแธฅ Muslim is โ€œWhoever dies without giving allegiance dies the death of pre-Islamic ignoranceโ€ (Muslim #4793).
  43. Al-Taftฤzฤnฤซ, Sharแธฅ al-สฟAqฤสพidย al-Nasafiyyaย (Karachi: Maktabat al-Bushrฤ, 1430/2009), 353โ€“54.
  44. Ibid.
  45. Ibid., 355.
  46. โ€œInna naแนฃb al-imฤm wฤjib qad สฟurifa wujลซbuh fฤซ al-sharสฟ bi-ijmฤสฟ al-แนฃaแธฅฤba wa-l-tฤbiสฟฤซn,โ€ Ibn Khaldun,ย al-Muqaddima, ed. Muแธฅammad al-Iskandarฤnฤซ (Beirut: Dฤr al-Kitฤb al-สฟArabฤซ,2006), 186 (Bk I, sec. 3, ch. 26); compare the translation by F. Rosenthal, abridged by N. J. Dawood in Ibn Khaldun,ย The Muqaddimah: An Introduction to Historyย (Princeton University Press, 1967), 156.
  47. H. A. R. Gibb,ย Studies on Islamic Civilizationย (Princeton Legacy Library, 1982 [orig. 1962]), 173.
  48. For a summary of these views, see แนขฤdiq Nuสฟmฤn,al-Khilฤfa al-Islฤmiyyaย (Cairo: Dฤr al-Salฤm, 2004), 26โ€“27; สฟAbdallฤh al-Dumayjฤซ,ย al-Imฤma al-สฟuแบ“mฤ สฟinda ahl al-sunnah wa-l-jamฤสฟaย (Riyadh: Dฤr แนฌayba, 1987), 45ff.
  49. สฟAlฤสพ al-Dฤซn al-แธคaแนฃkafฤซ (d. 1088/1677),ย al-Durr al-Mukhtฤr, 75.
  50. The helpful notion of โ€˜problem spaceโ€™ is proposed by anthropologist David Scott in hisย Conscripts of Modernityย (Duke University Press, 2004).
  51. See the section below entitled โ€œDid the Prophet Establish a State?โ€
  52. Al-Dhahabฤซ,ย Siyar, 3:372.
  53. Al-Bayhaqฤซ,ย Shuสฟab al-ฤซmฤn, 5:75114 vols., ed. Mukhtฤr al-Nadwฤซ (Riyadh: Maktaba al-Rushd, 2003), 10:15; Ibn Taymiyya,ย Minhฤj al-sunna, 1:146.
  54. Ibn Taymiyya,ย al-Siyฤsa al-sharสฟiyyaย , 161โ€“62.
  55. Al-Mฤwardฤซ,ย Aแธฅkฤm, 27.
  56. For details of the classical models of the caliphate and its political theory, see myย Politics, Law, and Community in Islamic Thought: The Taymiyyan Momentย (Cambridge University Press, 2012).
  57. For a discussion of the โ€œstrikingly egalitarianโ€ nature of early Islamic society and their Qurโ€™anic inspiration, โ€œaccentuated โ€ฆ by its conjunction with โ€ฆ Arab tribalism,โ€ see L. Marlow,ย Hierarchy and Egalitarianismย in Islamic Thoughtย (Cambridge University Press, 2002), 1-6; esp. 4.
  58. Bukhari #4359.
  59. Al-Kattฤnฤซ, 99. The same view is adopted by Ibn Taymiyya,ย Majmลซสฟ Fatฤwฤ, 35:33.
  60. Scholars, including al-Dhahabฤซ, al-Bayhaqฤซ, and Ibn Kathฤซr, all agree on the weakness of this hadith. See, e.g., al-Dhahabฤซ,ย Siyarย 3:131.
  61. Ibn Taymiyya,ย Majmลซสฟ Fatฤwฤ, 35:22.
  62. Michaelangelo Guida, โ€œSeyyid Bey and the Abolition of the Caliphate,โ€ย Middle Eastern Studiesย 44.2 (2008), 275โ€“89.
  63. Speaking of how quickly Atatรผrk killed off the religious scholars and transformed an entire culture, Hitler wrote admiringly in 1938 that the Turkish despot โ€œwas the first to show that it is possible to mobilize and regenerate the resources that a country has lost.โ€ โ€œAtatรผrk was a teacher,โ€ Hitler said. โ€œMussolini was his first and I his second student.โ€ Halil Karaveli, โ€œHitlerโ€™s Infatuation with Atatรผrk Revisited,โ€ย https://www.turkeyanalyst.org/publications/turkey-analyst-articles/item/367-hitler%E2%80%99s-infatuation-with-atat%C3%BCrk-revisited.htmlย (Accessed 7/4/19). See also Pankaj Mishra,ย Age of Anger: A History of the Present (New York: Farrar, Straus and Giroux, 2017), 131.
  64. James Broucek, โ€œThe Controversy of Shaykh ‘Ali ‘Abd Al-Raziq,โ€ Ph.D. Dissertation (University of Florida, 2012), 128.
  65. Those who wrote refutations were the leading scholars of the twentieth century: Aแธฅmad Shฤkir, Muแธฅammad Bakhฤซt al-Muแนญฤซสฟฤซ, Muแธฅammad Khiแธr แธคusayn, Rashฤซd Riแธฤ, แนฌฤhir ibn สฟฤ€shลซr. See Muแธฅammad สฟImฤraโ€™sย Maสฟrikat al-Islฤm wa-uแนฃลซl al-แธฅukmย (Cairo: Dฤr al-Shurลซq, 1989) for an analysis of the controversy in Arabic and a detailed presentation of the original arguments and their refutations.
  66. Quoted in Souad T. Ali,ย A Religion Not a Stateย (The University of Utah Press, 2009), 73. See also James Broucek, โ€œThe Controversy,โ€ 183; and Muแธฅammad สฟImฤra,ย Maสฟrikat al-Islฤm.
  67. For the historical evolution of theย tafsirย opinions on this verse, see my bookย Politics, Law, 52n59.
  68. แนฌabarฤซ,ย Tฤrฤซkhย (Dฤr al-Turฤth), 3:186-7.
  69. In all likelihood, สฟAbd al-Rฤziq had not read Juwaynฤซโ€™sย Ghiyฤth al-umamย (which would not have been available in published form), Ibn Taymiyyaโ€™sย Minhฤj, and most other classical works on the subject available to us, with the exception of al-Mฤwardฤซ and Ibn Khaldลซn, whom he cites. In personal communication, Prof. Ahmed El Shamsy of the University of Chicago informs me that whereas Ibn Taymiyyaโ€™sย Minhฤjย had been published by Bลซlฤq publishers in 1903-5, al-Juwaynฤซโ€™sย Ghiyฤthย would have been unavailable in published form at the time.
  70. สฟAbd al-Rฤaziq,ย al-Islฤm wa-Uuแนฃลซl al-แธคukm, quoted in Broucek, โ€œThe Controversy,โ€ 183; also สฟImฤra,ย Maสฟraikat al-Islฤm, 395ff.
  71. Mona Hassan,ย Longing for the Lost Caliphate: A Transregional Historyย (Princeton University Press, 2017).
  72. Reza Pankhurstโ€™sย The Inevitable Caliphate? A History of the Struggle for Global Islamic Union, 1924 to the Presentย (London: C. Hurst & Co. Publishers Ltd., 2013).
  73. Jacob Landau,ย Pan-Islamism: Ideology and Organizationย (Oxford: Clarendon Press, 1994).
  74. See, e.g., Sayyid,ย Recalling the Caliphate, 189.
  75. See, in particular, Sayyid,ย Recalling the Caliphate, chap. 5.
  76. Justine Marrozi, โ€œForget Lawrence of Arabia, hereโ€™s the real history of the Middle East and World War I,โ€ย The National, 26 Feb 2015, https://www.thenational.ae/arts-culture/the-long-read-forget-lawrence-of-arabia-here-s-the-real-history-of-the-middle-east-and-world-war-1-1.640119 (Accessed 18 Dec 2018).
  77. Fromkin,ย A Peace to End All Peace, 564.
  78. Wael Hallaq,ย The Impossible State.
  79. Ayubi,ย Overstating the Arab Stateย (1996); see also, Sayyid,ย Recalling, 146, who names the contemporary Arab governments โ€˜theย Mukhabarat state.โ€™
  80. See, for instance, Michael Cook,ย Ancient Religions, Modern Politics: The Islamic Case in Comparative Perspectiveย (Princeton University Press, 2014); Shadi Hamid,ย Islamic Exceptionalism: How the Struggle Over Islam Is Reshaping the Worldย (St. Martinโ€™s Press, 2016).
  81. A good reference in this regard, showing how the eventual triumph of the nation-state model was not inevitable, is Hendrik Spruyt,ย The Sovereign State and its Competitorsย (Princeton University Press, 2006). Thanks to Mohammed El-Sayed Bushra for this reference.
  82. Quentin Skinner, The Foundations of Modern Political Thought, vol. 1 (Cambridge University Press, 1978), ixโ€“x.
  83. Tilly,ย Coercion, Capital, and European States, AD 990-1990ย (Basil Blackwell, 1990), 1โ€“2.
  84. Carl Schmitt,ย Political Theology: Four Chapters on the Concept of Sovereignty, trans. George Schwab (MIT Press, 1985), 36.
  85. The modern state, furthermore, is a national state, one that presumably limits its loyaltyโ€”its โ€œavowal and disavowalโ€โ€”by national boundaries.
  86. Hallaq,ย The Impossible State, 155-6.
  87. Ibid.ย Citing and building on these studies, Hallaq has argued that the doctrine of the separation of powers is ineffective in the modern state in general, and this inefficacy has been thoroughly documented in the most institutionally advanced democracy, the United States (see chap. 3).
  88. John Maynard Keynes,ย The General Theory of Employment, Interest and Moneyย (Harvest/Harcourt Inc., 1964; orig. 1935), ย ch. 24, 383.
  89. สฟAbd al-Razzฤq al-Sanhลซrฤซ, quoted in Muแธฅammad สฟImฤra (ed.),ย Islฤmiyฤt al-Sanhลซrฤซ Bฤshฤ, vol. 1, 335โ€“37.
  90. Ibid.
  91. George Will,ย Theย Conservative Sensibilityย (2019), 157.
  92. For the kinds of conversation in political theory that these reflections require, see Chandran Kukathas,ย The Liberal Archipelago: A Theory of Diversity and Freedomย (Oxford University Press, 2003).
  93. This hadith is multiply reported (mutฤwatir), on the authority of many companions including สฟAlฤซ b. Abฤซ แนฌฤlib as recorded in, e.g., al-Bukhฤrฤซ,ย แนขaแธฅฤซแธฅ, Bukhari 6930 and Muslim,ย แนขaแธฅฤซแธฅ, 1066.

Discover more

Contention One: Ummatic Exceptionalism and the Prospect of Double Humiliation

July 17, 2024
Ovamir Anjum

Upcoming Colloquium

July 15, 2024
ummatics

Upcoming Meetups

July 15, 2024
ummatics

Search

Search

Sign up to our Newsletter